Sovereignty in Conflict(*)
Samantha Besson
European Integration online Papers (EIoP) Vol. 8 (2004) N° 15;
http://eiop.or.at/eiop/texte/2004-015a.htm
Date of Publication in EIoP: 23.9.2004
| Abstract | Back to homepage | PDF |
| This paper's comments page | Send your comment! to this paper |

Contents:


1

‘A different view would be that sovereignty and sovereign states, and the inexorable linkage of law with sovereignty and the state, have been but the passing phenomena of a few centuries, that their passing is by no means regrettable, and that current developments in Europe exhibit the possibility of going beyond all that. On this view, our passing beyond the sovereign state is to be considered a good thing, an entirely welcome development in the history of legal and political ideas.’(1)

Introduction

It is with this passage that Neil MacCormick started his now famous 1992 Chorley Lecture which was later published under the title Beyond the Sovereign State. He was then one of the first Anglo-American legal philosophers to analyse the legal and political nature of the European Union (EU) and to venture the possibility of doing so without the concept of legal and political sovereignty altogether.


2

His concept of post-sovereignty has gradually become very influential in Europe(2) and has recently led many authors to compete in finding the right vocabulary to pinpoint the very specificity of the shift in sovereignty which has characterized European politics over the years.(3) Sovereignty is clearly en vogue and even more so since constitutional talk has made its way to the European front stage, thus raising the spectre of European unitary sovereignty, on the one hand, and hence of renewed threats to national sovereignty, on the other. In fact, never has sovereignty been as fashionable as since its explanatory and normative force first came into doubt and its knell was tolled in the European Union. What makes sovereignty such a contestable concept is its very paradox: the high degree and diversity of criticism raised against state sovereignty for the past fifty years both in practice and theory, on the one hand, and its remarkable resilience in post-national(4) political debate and legal discourse, on the other. As Neil Walker rightly observes in his recent book Sovereignty in Transition, ‘the idea of sovereignty cannot just be wished away. […] It is the very challenge to the old order that demands such urgent re-examination of the building blocks of that order ’.(5)

This concern for the future of sovereignty is not new, however, and goes beyond the question of the political nature of the European Union.(6) For a long time the concept or principle(7) of (state) sovereignty was regarded as the cornerstone of both national and international political and legal organization, on the one hand, and of modern political thought, on the other;(8) it was the state’s ‘normal’ condition(9) to be the supreme power or ultimate authority in political and legal matters, whether internally or externally. The precursor of the current ‘international community(10) ’ resembled a ‘society’ of equal and independent states sovereign both on the outside and the inside.(11) In fact, not only was sovereignty regarded as a norm, but its content itself was perceived as self-evident and applicable to all matters of daily governance.(12) Of course, sovereignty has always been limited.(13) For a long time, however, these limitations have been regarded as inherent to the concept of sovereignty and as jeopardizing neither its function nor its justification.(14)

Recently, however, sovereignty has been subject to growing challenges both in theory and in practice. Over the last fifty years or so, lawyers, political theorists and specialists of international relations have become more and more divided on the issue of state sovereignty and sovereignty in general. The international community’s power has been constantly reinforced to the detriment of state sovereignty; this has happened through power transfers from states to international or supranational organisations such as the EU(15) , the development of ius cogens(16) and of the international community’s ‘constitution’(17) , the reinforcement of the principle of humanitarian intervention, the emergence of the concept of ‘failed state’, economic or legal globalization and, finally, the development of new international and transnational actors such as NGOs or multinational corporations.(18) Conflicts of sovereignty have increased in practice and conflicting claims to ultimate authority on all sorts of matters constitute a permanent feature in the now pervasive regimes of multilevel governance(19) . This is illustrated by the Kompetenz Kompetenz crisis and the recurrence of constitutional conflicts in the EU, i.e. conflicts of claims over matters falling into the field of ultimate national and European constitutional competence such as fundamental rights or basic principles.(20) Besides these threats on external sovereignty posed by the development of supra-state and post-state political entities, the emergence of infra-state claims to authority has contributed even further to the fragmentation of internal sovereignty.(21)

With this shift in authority away from the state to new sub-state, supra-state, post-state(22) and non-state entities, the question is whether the concept of ultimate authority or sovereignty is to be abandoned or, on the contrary, retained and, if so, in which form. Faced with these changes, most authors still regard the state as a central feature of the new national and international order, be it in the context of the conclusion or of the implementation of international law.(23)

 

3

Some claim, however, that sovereignty has become obsolete in the new post-Westphalian and pluralist constitutional order where different legal orders overlap within the same territory and population(24) , and that it should therefore be abandoned.(25) Although they usually refer to state sovereignty, some extend this verdict to sovereignty in general. Some authors even call for the adoption of new concepts that are more apt to seize the new national and international organization.(26) Others, on the contrary, advocate the concept of sovereignty’s continuity and emphasize the central role it continues to play in the current international structure.(27)

This theoretical and practical state of affairs has gradually given rise to a flourishing literature.(28) The issue has not yet been explored from every angle, however.(29) The debate raises interesting questions about the nature of the concept of sovereignty and its relationship to the changing political and legal reality of the state and the international order more generally. Viewed from a wider angle, it is the applicability of statist concepts like sovereignty to the post-national reality which is thrown into doubt and it reveals the necessity to translate those concepts into conceptions that do not constrain this new reality and hence to develop a post-national jurisprudence.(30) In this context, the question this paper addresses is the following: is it really necessary to choose, as most do, between, on the one hand, rejecting the concept of sovereignty in order to enter the era of post-sovereignty, and, on the other, maintaining it as it is, despite intense changes in the international order? Consequently, the paper aims at exploring a third way that would allow us to escape from the two types of dualism that contrast state and sovereignty, first, and rejecting and saving sovereignty, second.(31)

The first opposition will not be dealt with in great detail in this paper –the issues it raises have already been addressed extensively elsewhere.(32) It contrasts abandoning the concept of state in order to save sovereignty in a post-statist world, with abandoning the concept of sovereignty to save post-sovereign states.(33) The idea here is, on the contrary, to consider the capacity of adaptation of both the concepts of sovereignty and state.(34) Both may be withheld and remain important in practice. No one can deny that the state remains one of the key elements of the international order(35) nor that it is necessary to have a sovereign or ultimate authority(36) to settle conflicts. It is important, however, to realize that both concepts can evolve; this can occur either symmetrically when state and sovereignty are linked, or asymmetrically when they are dissociated as is often the case nowadays –it suffices to look at the Swiss cantons and at the European Union to see that some states are not sovereign and some sovereign authorities are not states.(37)

It is the second opposition between maintaining and rejecting sovereignty that will be addressed in more depth and that will hopefully be overcome.(38) It relies on a far too rigid and static approach to the concept of sovereignty. The choice should not be between retaining the concept in its state-like unitary and absolute conception thus seeking a Kelsenian or Schmittian finalité(39), and requiring an exclusive choice between national and European claims to sovereignty for instance, on the one hand, and abandoning sovereignty completely, on the other, thus ignoring the epistemic and normative resilience of the concept both in practice and theory.(40) The alternative is not to choose between realizing the tyranny of statist concepts like sovereignty and rejecting them en bloc, on the one hand, and their perpetuation in their rigid statist conceptions without further translation and adaptation to the post-national context, on the other.(41) It should be possible to retain the concept of sovereignty while allowing it to fluctuate along the lines of current changes in the international community and to adapt to the new reality of constitutional pluralism in Europe;(42) it has evolved in this way in the past without ever being rejected for doing so.(43) As a result, authors usually do not spend much time elaborating on what they take sovereignty to mean in general.(44) One finds limited references to supreme authority or ultimate power.(45) These two definitions refer to very different facets of sovereignty which correspond to its normative and empirical dimensions.(46) This built-in flexibility of the concept is even more important as the new international reality has not stabilized yet.(47)


4

If it is possible to conceive of such a third intermediary approach to sovereignty in a post-national order, how should this new form of sovereignty be conceptualized? Recently, some authors have explored this third path, in the European context in particular,(48) but without yet providing a detailed account of the nature of this new form of sovereignty and of its practical implications. This paper also aims therefore to develop a more complete account of the complex relationship among sovereign authorities in the same political and legal community. The cornerstone of this account is captured by the idea of sovereignty in conflict: rather than understanding constitutional conflicts and other clashes of sovereignty as a problem requiring either a unitary sovereign resolution or the rejection of all sovereign resolutions, the co-existence, competition and mutual adjustment of conflicting claims of sovereignty should be regarded as a normal and desirable political and legal condition. Conflicts over the concept of sovereignty and competing claims to political and legal sovereignty in practice(49) are to be understood as the best way to ensure unity in diversity through a reflexive and cooperative decision-making process in each case.(50)

To address these issues, the paper’s argument is five-pronged. The first section examines the relationship between conceptual analysis and political and legal change (Section 1.). The second section addresses the concept of essentially contestable concept (Section 2.). In the following section, I argue that the concept of sovereignty is essentially contestable, assess its different dimensions and draw some implications for the concept’s centrality in our daily political and legal debates (Section 3.). Finally, in the last section, I discuss the future of sovereignty in the European Union in the light of the theoretical conclusions of the paper (Section 4.).

1. Reality change and conceptual continuity to contents list

It is important at the opening of the present paper to start by clarifying the relationship between a political and legal concept like sovereignty and the object to which it refers. Of course, a certain distance between the philosophical analysis of a concept and its legal and political use(51) is unavoidable.(52) This paper’s starting point, however, is to claim that a minimal relationship must be maintained between a concept and its practice, or else political and legal analysis would become avoid.(53)

Until now, political and legal philosophers have not been very clear on what this relationship should be. A majority of authors argues that legal concepts are both descriptive in a first stage and prescriptive in a second stage when they constrain reality. Their function is to determine through observation and then to prescribe what the essential criteria of those concepts are. In the case of sovereignty, for instance, conceptual analysis is about determining the essential qualities of sovereignty by reference to its reality and then to capture them in conceptual criteria.(54) These in turn will entail certain prescriptions about what a sovereign state or a sovereign legal order can be.(55) It remains of course possible to adapt and revise the meaning of concepts whose use fluctuates. Once a concept has been reassessed, however, its function becomes prescriptive again and implies normative constraints on practice.(56) Other authors take a more realistic stance and regard legal concepts as mere reflections and descriptions of legal and political reality. Any other approach would amount to a purely metaphysical construction whose validity could not be tested in any objective way. According to legal realists, the task of legal philosophical concepts is to describe those institutions and principles on which positive law and political practice rely effectively.(57)

 

5

Neither approach is entirely satisfactory, especially when taken to apply to the concept of sovereignty. Intense recent developments in international and European law reveal the limits of both approaches of political and legal concepts.(58) While the prescriptive approach aims at testing legal and practical reality against a pre-existing model of the state and sovereignty, the descriptive one seeks to retrieve the content of the concepts of state and sovereignty entirely from a new reality. Both approaches put sovereignty at risk by, on the one hand, either corseting reality too tightly thus prematurely condemning new political and legal practices and cutting sovereignty off too early from reality by redefining it too strictly(59) or, on the other, by emptying it from any content whatsoever and thus limiting any possibility of conceptual continuity in the political and legal realm. It follows therefore that sovereignty is not a merely prescriptive political concept that insists on constraining political and legal reality according to an abstract standard. Nor is it a purely descriptive political concept that refers to an independent and objective reality. Sovereignty is more than what those entities which claim to be sovereign actually are, but it is less than what pre-existing abstract standards of sovereignty may require it should be.(60) Walker refers to these two ways of misunderstanding sovereignty as the descriptive fallacy and the fallacy of abstraction.(61)

Although neither approach is founded per se, they can be reconciled and propounded together.(62) Like other legal and political concepts, sovereignty should account for political and legal reality and should therefore be able to fluctuate with it, although this mirroring effect cannot always be perfect. This does not mean, however, that the concept of sovereignty should not retain a certain normative impact on political and legal reality, although this impact should not lead to corseting political reality.(63) A third and combined approach to legal and political concepts like sovereignty is therefore needed to reconcile the normative role of sovereignty with the profound changes in the political and legal reality. Sovereignty, like other central political and legal concepts, should be neither entirely closed nor entirely open; it should neither encompass all changes of reality, nor exclude any change of its paradigms, i.e. of its central exemplars in practice. Sovereignty is therefore best understood as what one calls in philosophy of language an essentially contestable concept.(64) Because the concept expresses one or many values it aims at protecting, different evaluations and conceptions of it can be given and this contestable nature is one of its main features.(65)

Sovereignty should be entitled to remain the same concept and hence establish a conceptual framework in which debates can take place,(66) while also fluctuating at the same time through changes of paradigms and of conceptions;(67) the essential contestability of sovereignty ‘can account for both change and for continuity in change(68)’. Instead of understanding sovereignty as a mere fact or as a purely normative standard, the concept’s essential contestability makes it possible to account for its institutional and discursive resilience while also respecting its normative input;(69) some authors also refer to the double hermeneutic of sovereignty(70) and the fact that the concept of sovereignty is not only an interpretation of the world, but that this interpretation is already part of that world and of its ‘sedimented discourse(71)’.

 
 
 
 
 
 
 

6

2. The concept of ‘essentially contestable concept’to contents list

2.1. A definition of the concept

One of the objectives of this paper is to establish that the concept of sovereignty not only amounts to a complex and normative concept, but also that it is an essentially contestable concept. As such, it is a concept that not only expresses a normative standard and whose conceptions differ from one person to the other, but whose correct application is to create disagreement over its correct application or, in other words, over what the concept is itself. The concept of ‘essentially contestable concept’ owes its original formulation to William Gallie.(72) Since then, the concept has been re-used and further developed in moral and political philosophy,(73) but also in legal philosophy(74) – although not always in a discerning manner.

Traditional approaches to normative concepts, like the concepts of democracy or justice, are extremely cautious about the role of contestation. They do not consider normative contestation as part of those concepts’ correct application. On the contrary, most authors distinguish between the phase of descriptive conceptual analysis, on the one hand, through which it is possible to identify and establish minimal criteria of application of normative concepts in an objective way and the normative discussion of these concepts, on the other, during which phase only it is possible to contest the assessment of the values those concepts encompass and protect.(75) It is crucial to understand, however, that disputes which surround normative concepts cannot be compared to those about criterial concepts such as ‘book’ or ‘chair’. In those cases, there is sufficient consensus to accept the existence of minimal criteria of correct application and contestation over those criteria can be explained in terms of error.(76) In the case of normative concepts, however, contestation goes to the heart of the concepts and is not limited to its peripheral cases of application,(77) without it being necessarily evident that those contesting so-called criteria of application are necessarily mistaken.(78) It is implausible in those conditions to separate prior conceptual analysis from normative contestation.(79)

To claim essential contestability, it is surely not enough to say that a concept is normative; it is a necessary condition for it to encompass one or many values, but it is not a sufficient condition since some normative standards might be pre-established in a criterial way. Nor is it enough to refer to the evidence of its historical and cultural variability and the disputes over its correct application. Empirical and contingent claims like these would be claims of mere contestedness. To claim that a concept is contestable is to make the analytical claim that debates about the criteria of correct application of a concept are inconclusive.(80) Finally, to claim that a concept’s subject matter is such that there are always good reasons for someone to dispute the propriety of any of its uses, is to claim its essential contestability; the ‘essentiality’ of its contestability does not mean that the disagreements that surround its meaning are irresolvable,(81) but that, on the one hand, disputes about the meaning of the concept go to the heart of the matter and can generate rival paradigms and criteria of application and that, on the other, it is part of the very nature of the concept to be contested and to raise questions as to its nature.(82)

In Connolly’s slightly refined version(83) of Gallie’s definition of essentially contestable concepts,(84) a concept is essentially contestable

  1. when it is appraisive in that the state of affairs it describes is a valued achievement which is initially variously describable,(85)
  2. when this state of affairs is internally complex in that its characterization involves references to several dimensions of meaning(86) as opposed to judging something to be ‘red’, and
  3. when its criteria of application – whether shared or disputed- are themselves relatively open, enabling parties to interpret even shared criteria differently, both across a range of familiar cases and as new and unforeseen circumstances arise.

7

2.2 Some implicationsto contents list

After this brief clarification of the concept of essentially contestable concepts, it is important to discuss two implications of the use of such concepts.

First of all, the recognition of the existence of essentially contestable concepts does not imply taking a sceptical stance.(87) It is entirely consistent with the existence of objective values; although the concept of justice is contestable and although parties to the disagreement hold reasonable but conflicting conceptions of it, this does not prevent one of them from being right and the other wrong. This explains why the recognition of essentially contestable concepts on the part of participants in the political discourse is compatible with the willingness to deliberate and exchange arguments with others; one may hope to convince others without, however, necessarily having to believe that it is possible to find the right conception in all cases.(88)

Secondly, the recognition of the essentially contestable nature of a concept is an analytical statement. It implies the possibility of conceiving a concept as normative, that is to say as encompassing a contestable value. It does not therefore protect against analytical mistakes or errors of judgement.(89) It is important to note that what enables the parties to know that their disagreement about an essentially contestable concept pertains to the same concept and not to two different concepts lies in the exemplars or paradigms they share before starting the discussion. These are provided by those central cases in which the concept clearly applies. What distinguishes paradigms from criteria and agreement over them(90), however, is the evolutive nature of the former; paradigms adapt to new circumstances and can be entirely ousted in favour of new paradigms in the course of discussion, provided these changes are made gradually and that some minimal paradigms are shared to start the discussion.(91)

3. Sovereignty qua essentially contestable concept to contents list

There are three main conditions to be fulfilled for the concept of sovereignty to be regarded as an essentially contestable concept: the concept must be normative, intrinsically complex and a-criterial.

3.1. Sovereignty qua normative concept

As a normative concept, the concept of sovereignty expresses and incorporates one or many values that it seeks to implement in practice and according to which political situations should be evaluated.(92) These values are diverse and include, among others, democracy, human rights, equality and self-determination.

Concept determination amounts therefore to more than a mere description of the concept’s core application criteria; it implies an evaluation of a state of affairs on the basis of sovereignty’s incorporated values. What lies behind the prima facie categorical use of central political and legal concepts like sovereignty are not facts that should be established, but conceptions and interpretations that should be evaluated and maybe amended in order to account better for the values encompassed by these concepts.(93) It follows therefore that the determination of the concept of sovereignty cannot be distinguished from the values it entails and from the normative discussion that generally prevails around it.(94)


8

3.2. Sovereignty qua complex conceptto contents list

The second condition for the essentially contestable nature of the concept of sovereignty is the complexity of the concept. The concept of sovereignty clearly encompasses different dimensions of meaning by contrast to a simple concept like ‘chair’. There are three main dimensions one should mention: the concept of sovereignty qua outcome, the concept of sovereignty qua question and the concept of sovereignty qua value. Sovereignty is therefore at once a result, a question as to what this result should be and a justification of this result in terms of values.(95)

3.2.1. The complexity of sovereignty qua outcome to contents list

The difficulty of general concepts like the concept of sovereignty is that they give rise to a plurality of criteria and principles whose content is extremely contestable. These different criteria constitute what can be referred to as the concept qua outcome or result-concept of sovereignty; they contribute to determining what sovereignty is as a state of affairs or achievement.(96) These criteria qualify the minimal and relatively uncontroversial statement of sovereignty as the ultimate and supreme authority or power of decision and are sometimes described as constitutive rules of sovereignty.(97) They are heavily contested in practice, not only per se, but also inside each group of oppositions where different conceptions can be defended.

3.2.1.1. Political and legal sovereignty

Political and legal sovereignty have always been closely linked in the history of the concept; most theories either derive legal sovereignty from political sovereignty or vice-versa. The paradox of pouvoir constituant and pouvoir constitué or of rule sovereignty and ruler sovereignty is inextricably tied to the claim to sovereignty; political sovereignty is difficult to conceive without rules to exercize and constrain that sovereignty, but legal sovereignty is hard to fathom without a political power to establish its legal rules in the first place.

Different accounts have been given of the priority between political and legal sovereignty across the centuries and have contributed to perpetuating the centrality of the concept of sovereignty. Some authors have even argued that this paradox and mutual claim are testimony of the conceptual incoherence of sovereignty.(98) While Austin and command theorists give priority to political sovereignty over legal sovereignty, Hart and recent positivists give priority to legal sovereignty over political sovereignty.(99) Other authors like Kelsen argue, on the contrary, that political and legal sovereignty are identical and cannot therefore be put in any relationship of priority.(100) More recently, some authors have tried to dissociate legal and political sovereignty and re-associate legal to institutional sovereignty.(101) At a time when state and law, and more generally the political and the legal tend to drift apart in practice, as demonstrated by the emergence of the European legal order, the development of lex mercatoria and other forms of transnational global law,(102) the sovereignty of law must somehow be able to be kept conceptually distinct from the state and maybe from political sovereignty. The question that arises is the following: while it must be possible to distinguish political and legal sovereignty from each other, is it possible to do so without giving one priority over the other but without, however, having to give one up for the other?(103)

 
 
 

9

The law remains a political instrument and creation, whether at the national, European or international level. As a consequence, legal sovereignty will most of the time match political sovereignty.(104) It is difficult to see how the sovereignty of European law, for instance, can be pertinent outside its relationship to political sovereignty in the EU in the field of competence of the legal norm in question. Conversely, however, it is difficult to understand how political sovereignty can be exercized in the EU without legal sovereignty, in particular with respect to the constitutional determination of the structure of political power and competences.(105) Sovereignty amounts to the competence of a political entity,(106) hence the idea of ‘competence of the competence’ (‘Kompetenz Kompetenz’) and the difficulty to establish one’s own competences without legal sovereignty. It follows therefore that legal and political sovereignty, even though they are conceptually distinct, are not separable in practice in the long run.(107) This also implies that when they are both granted, neither of them can be given priority over the other. There is, in other words, an imperfect relationship between the two forms of sovereignty.(108)

In fact, this interpretation of the relationship between political and legal sovereignty solves a long-standing paradox or at least makes the most of it.(109) Sovereignty should be situated at the boundary between politics and law or between democracy and rights, rather than being clearly embedded in one or the other. As Walker argues, the double claim to political and legal sovereignty should ‘be viewed more constructively as the conceptual key to sovereignty as a dynamic process of mutual constitution and mutual containment of law and politics’(110). It is crucial for the legitimating effect of the competitive and cooperative exercize of sovereignty in the EU that it be subordinated neither entirely to a legal and normative division of competences nor entirely to political power and to the rule of the majority.(111) On the contrary, both legal and political sovereignty should be kept in tension and mutual relationship for the values protected by both forms of sovereignty to be enforced.(112)

3.2.1.2. External and internal sovereignty

Traditionally, the concept of sovereignty has always operated in two distinct ways: sovereignty can be exercized in relation to one’s internal affairs, on the one hand, but also to one’s external affairs, on the other. Even though there exists a historical and link between these two forms of sovereignty, it is important to distinguish between them conceptually. First of all, different institutions exercize sovereignty in both cases: the executive acts as a sovereign in external affairs, while it is usually the legislative which is regarded as sovereign in internal affairs. Hence the difficulty there is sometimes of distinguishing between parliamentary sovereignty on the inside and national sovereignty on the outside.(113) Secondly, their functions differ; whereas internal sovereignty pertains to all political and legal matters, external sovereignty usually only relates to questions of cooperation among distinct sovereign entities. Finally, external sovereignty can less easily be described as final or ultimate; it can only be equally ultimate since a sovereign can only co-exist as an equal to other sovereigns.(114) In internal affairs, however, sovereignty is usually final.

Although both forms of sovereignty may be kept conceptually distinct,(115) they cannot be separated in practice; for there to be external sovereignty, there must be internal sovereignty and vice-versa.(116) Without external sovereignty, indeed, the internal sovereign cannot define the latter and without internal sovereignty in the constitutional determination of competences, there cannot be an external sovereign and no human rights limitations in particular.(117) It is difficult therefore to place one before the other in an order of emergence.(118) This issue is particularly relevant in the European context. Contrary to federal states, the European Union was not created through the gradual concession of Member States’ external sovereignty.(119)


10

Most transfers of competence relate to internal matters. Many authors have deduced from this that the only kind of sovereignty one should be concerned with in the European context is internal sovereignty.(120) This, however, underestimates the strength of the bond between these two forms of sovereignty; with less internal sovereignty, external sovereignty is also affected and has gradually shrunk at national level.(121)

3.2.1.3. Absolute and limited sovereignty

The question of the degree of power and amount of competence necessary for an entity to become or remain sovereign has given rise to a long controversy in the history of the concept. According to some authors, sovereignty can only be absolute. This is the classical conception of sovereignty one finds in Bodin and Hobbes in particular. This position does not hold, however, once internal sovereignty is understood together with external sovereignty. External sovereignty can never be regarded as ultimate or final; it is inherently limited since public international law and external sovereignty imply each other.(122) Without rules of international law, sovereignty would be reduced to mere factual power.(123) These inherent limitations to external sovereignty have also become constitutive limitations to internal sovereignty(124) given the internal impact of many external agreements, such as human rights instruments, for instance. Finally, this absolute conception of sovereignty cannot account satisfactorily for new developments in political and legal organization. More precisely, it ignores the plurality of sources of law and power in the new world order and what is often referred as constitutional pluralism, i.e. the post-Westphalian order characterized by the co-existence of autonomous constitutional orders in the same political and legal community and territory.(125)

In response to these difficulties, some authors have suggested the idea of limited sovereignty. The problem arising from this model is to know when sovereignty is so limited or fragmented that there can be no talk of sovereignty anymore. The concept of sovereignty implies a certain amount of intensity or of competence over a range of matters.(126) As we saw before, sovereignty is a general competence, i.e. a competence to determine one’s particular competence; as such, it requires a minimal level of control over those competences. In other words, is there a threshold below which sovereignty is emptied of any content and if so, where does it lie? Some authors have denied this identification of sovereignty with a threshold-concept.(127) One argument against it may reside in the contestation of sovereignty and hence of this minimal threshold. As I explained before, however, the essentially contestable nature of the concept of sovereignty is an analytical statement which is perfectly compatible with the recognition of the normative content of the concept and of its contestability. One might therefore consider that these minimal threshold constraints are part of the analytical framework one has to assume when using a contestable concept, i.e. that it is a concept, that it protects certain values, that it is contestable, etc.(128)

It remains difficult, however, to establish where the minimal threshold of sovereignty lies.(129) Some authors merely agree with the idea of a threshold without providing more information.(130) Others enumerate different competences which might constitute a minimal threshold of authority and be used to identify a sovereign entity.(131) They mention territorial supremacy, control over nationality acquisition, immigration control or national security.(132) Others on the contrary mention different competences, but add that their absence does not affect the existence of sovereignty.(133) Generally, the problem is the absence of consensus and the constant change in the paradigmatic constitutive elements of sovereignty. The content of the threshold cannot but remain contestable and different paradigms have been used at different times in the history of the concept of sovereignty.(134) For instance, purely territorial sovereignty has gradually been replaced by a differentiated and overlapping functional form of sovereignty in the EU.(135) It is therefore one of the characteristics of sovereignty to be a threshold-concept, whose threshold itself is contestable over time.


11

3.2.1.4. Unitary and divided sovereignty

Another related distinction pertains to the divisibility of sovereignty.(136) In fact, both issues are very closely connected and often conflated. Traditional and recent literature refer to absolute sovereignty to mean unlimited sovereignty as much as indivisible sovereignty.(137) For the sake of clarity, I will refer to absolute sovereignty by contrast to limited sovereignty only, although divided sovereignty can obviously no longer be deemed absolute. The opposition between unitary and divided sovereignty is a traditional one. Authors like Bodin or Hobbes fear the division of sovereignty as much as its limitation. In a post-Westphalian world where competences are not only limited, but also shared, however, such fears have become obsolete. Divisions of competences are indeed the rule in the European Union and beyond(138). This applies in almost all domains and at all degrees of authority. Sometimes, it is even more than a matter of fact, as shown by the possibility to transfer sovereign competences provided by Art. 23 of the German Basic Law.(139) Of course, some have argued that sovereignty is not strictly divided in those cases, but that it is its exercize that is delegated and hence divided,(140) thus preserving sovereignty’s unity.(141) This argument cannot, however, account for the extremely high degree and complexity of transfers of competence in the EU in particular.(142)

In response to the limits of the unitary approach to sovereignty, the idea of disaggregation and reaggregation of sovereignty has been brought forward by some to grasp the poly-centred dimension of contemporary sovereignty.(143) The problem with this kind of model of pooled, divided or shared sovereignty, however, is that by being everywhere, it seems that sovereignty is nowhere particularly important.(144) As Walker argues, pooled sovereignty sits ‘uneasily with the sense of sovereignty as a unifying and self-identifying claim made on behalf of the polity’(145). It is important therefore to account for a minimal threshold of competences which may neither be limited nor shared. As we will see later, there is a third approach to sovereignty in a post-Westphalian world that is neither unitary nor pooled but that does not abandon the idea of ultimate power and authority altogether; it is the idea of cooperative sovereignty. It is crucial to understand that the possibility of conflicts and divisions in the absence of a unitary conception of sovereignty need not be conceived as problem; as we will see, these conflicts belong to democratic life and we should make the most of them by promoting dialogue and duties of mutual adjustment in plurality.(146)

3.2.1.5. Institutional and popular sovereignty

This last distinction goes back to Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s account of political sovereignty and the dissociation of the original sovereignty of the demos from that of political institutions. According to this conception, political authorities’ sovereignty is transferred to them through a social contract which binds them and holds them accountable to the original sovereign: the people.(147) Through the social contract, the people constitutes itself as a distinct entity and sovereign while also transferring the exercize of its sovereignty to a constituted institutional sovereign. Thus, political and popular sovereignty are reunited, and then artificially separated in order to bind the sovereign to the people. Political sovereignty becomes a mere reflection of popular sovereignty; if the sovereign does not respect popular will, it risks losing its attributions. Sovereignty and democracy are clearly bound and sovereignty can both be deemed absolute when it is original, and limited when it corresponds to derived political or institutional sovereignty.

 

12

The principle of popular sovereignty presents the advantage of providing a ready link between democracy and political participation, on the one hand, and sovereignty, on the other. It also lies at the origins of the connection between sovereignty and self-determination or national autonomy.(148) These issues play out in the European context where the democratic specificities of the European construction require conceptual imagination with respect to the relationships between national and European popular sovereignties and the many European demoi.(149)

3.2.2. The complexity of sovereignty qua question to contents list

This second form of complexity is generated by the different answers that can be given to the question of what the best allocation of power is in each case, i.e. the different interpretations given to sovereignty qua outcome. The concept of sovereignty’s specificity is that it does not only consist of a way to evaluate an outcome, but also of a normative question about what this outcome should be and how it should be reached.(150) It is a question-concept or a reflexive concept in the sense that it is part of its nature and application to constantly question what sovereignty is about.(151)

3.2.2.1. From sovereignty qua question to subsidiarity

Given the complexity of the question of sovereignty, the concept’s correct application implies a constant debate about how best to achieve sovereignty. Paradoxically, this approach to sovereignty is not without resemblance with the principle that is usually taken to be its opposite:(152) the principle of subsidiarity.(153) The principle of subsidiarity is just as contestable a concept as that of sovereignty(154) , maybe intentionally so.(155) As a concept of power distribution, it is usually said to date back to the social and political theory of the Catholic Church, although both concepts no longer have much in common.(156) In a nutshell, the principle of subsidiarity is a power allocation principle: it requires that the entity that can best achieve a task be in charge of it.(157) It was introduced in European law by Art. 5(2) of the Consolidated Version of the Treaty establishing the European Community (ECT). It constitutes one of the key principles of the division of competences in the European Union; in the absence of exclusive competence, European authorities can only take action when the objectives of the proposed action cannot be satisfactorily attained by Member States and therefore have a better chance of being achieved by the Community.(158)

Read together with sovereignty qua reflexive concept, the principle of subsidiarity implies a test of efficiency in power allocation. In each case, the sovereign authority will be that authority which can realize the objective in the most efficient way.(159) This applies to cases where different authorities claim sovereignty on the same issues, without any preference for the larger or smaller unit. For instance, since democratic rule is one of the shared values protected by sovereignty, sovereignty may require allowing another authority to decide in a specific case if that endows those affected by that decision with a stronger voice and hearing. This does not mean that subsidiarity is itself a democratic principle; it may ensure the best realization of democracy possible, but cannot be identified with it. Just as one needs to identify a sovereign power before subsidiarity can apply, one needs to identify a democratic one for subsidiarity to ensure the best democratic allocation of power.(160)

This allocation of competences may be achieved through mutual adjustment and consistency in principle with one authority abiding by the other’s past decisions on the issue, but also through actual delegation and transfer of competences;(161) sovereignty may indeed have to be transferred in parts to ensure the best realization of the values it protects.(162) In all cases, this decision is a sovereign one, because it is not pre-decided and sovereignty has not been shared or divided; questioning, emulation and cooperation are part of the regular exercize of sovereignty.(163) As MacCormick argues, therefore,


13

‘Europe’s new way of parcelling out powers opens the door to a conception of subsidiarity that could gradually acquire real teeth. That is to say, once a process of sharing out powers is seriously undertaken, one can ask the question where it is best for the common good that a particular power be exercised.’ (164)

3.2.2.2. Cooperative sovereignty

Respecting subsidiarity in the fulfilment of one’s sovereign tasks and duties can be considered as part of the correct application of the concept of sovereignty.(165) Because the preference is not necessarily given to the smaller unit, but to the best substantive outcome, this combined reading of sovereignty and subsidiarity can provide just the right balance between integration and subsidiarity.(166) Ever since its creation, the European Union has been oscillating between strong unification, on the one hand, and subsidiarity, on the other. As the European Union is deeply pluralist and disagreement-ridden, none of these alternatives has been in itself very promising; unification would undermine the flourishing of a political culture within Member States and subsidiarity would undermine it between them. Hence the attractiveness of a conception of sovereignty that would enable Europe to escape from this dualism between alienation and fragmentation, and this is precisely what cooperative sovereignty can provide.

What the relationship between sovereignty qua question and subsidiarity reveals indeed is that gradually the exercize of sovereignty has turned from an individual exercize into a cooperative enterprise.(167) This corresponds to the more general development of multilevel governance in a post-national constellation;(168) sovereign political entities can no longer exercize their traditional competences and functions alone, especially, but not only, when these overlap within the same territory and apply to the same legal and political community.(169) This community encompasses all sovereign authorities which are active in that community and whose rules and decisions affect the same people in that community. This is the case of European and national authorities in the EU or of international and national authorities in the global world. In these conditions, sovereign authorities need to collaborate with other sovereign political and legal entities when applying the same rules and principles in this pluralist constitutional order(170) and this gives rise to a participative or cooperative form of sovereignty.(171) This form of sovereignty triggers duties of cooperation on the part of entities which cannot ensure the protection of all the values they should protect, as much as on the part of entities which can help the former protect those values they share.(172) They should all be seen as working towards the same end: the realization of their shared sovereign values and principles, such as human rights or democratic standards.(173)

Only when understood in this cooperative way, can sovereignty be the reflexive and dynamic concept it is, stimulating constant challenging of the allocation of power, thus putting into question others’ sovereignty as well as one’s own.(174) This common exercize of political sovereignty is then reflected in the structure of the relationship between the different legal orders at stake; none of them is ultimately and entirely submitted to another. This kind of legal cooperation reveals the possibility of a non-hierarchically organized plurality of legal orders, which may individually remain hierarchical in their internal structure or in their relationship to international law(175) , but which relate to one another in a heterarchical way.(176)

 
 
 
 
 

14

3.2.3. The complexity of sovereignty qua value to contents list

3.2.3.1. The plurality of values of sovereignty

This last form of complexity flows from the plurality of values and normative standards that the concept of sovereignty protects and to which it is held accountable. This gives a new significance to the 17th century conception of sovereignty qua function rather than personified authority;(177) it is not the identity of the political entity which determines its sovereignty, but only the values it pursues under the umbrella of sovereignty.

Understood along these lines, sovereignty is not an empirical end in itself, but should be exercized to protect the different values which constitute its justification.(178) These include equality, human rights,(179) democracy,(180) national self-determination(181) or other values protected in the international community(182) such as tolerance, stability or cultural pluralism.(183) It is actually part of the complexity of sovereignty qua question for the values it protects to be contestable; in the course of the history of contestation of the concept, normative standards have not always been part of the concept of sovereignty and whenever they were, they were not always the same.

3.2.3.2. Human rights protection qua criterion of sovereignty

The co-existence and interdependence of a plurality of sovereign states give rise to difficulties which call for consensually agreed upon rules of international law. Besides those conventional rules, however, the growing interdependence of states has also generated further rules of ius cogens, or more precisely, a universal human rights code, which apply to all sovereign states, whether they accept them or not.(184) Since, as we have seen before, those limits are now regarded as inherent to external sovereignty, they have also consequently become a constitutive element of internal sovereignty for reasons related to those two facets of sovereignty’s conceptual connection.(185) Human rights constitute one of the values incorporated and protected by contemporary political and legal sovereignty, that is to say one of the goals of the exercize of sovereignty(186) and one of the standards according to which we should hold that exercize accountable.(187) This relationship between the justification of sovereignty and the protection of human rights has different implications for cases where sovereign authorities overlap in their areas of sovereignty while being held accountable to the same human rights instruments and fundamental principles.(188) The most important implication is that any activity related to the potentially cooperative exercize of sovereignty should aim at the protection of human rights as far as possible.(189) This applies to the transfer of competences of sovereignty, as much as to the intervention in case of negligence of these competences.

Primarily, the legitimacy of a transfer of sovereign competences from one political entity to the next depends on the conditions inherent in the exercize of sovereignty and these include the protection of human rights. Both the entity which transfers and the entity which receives sovereign competences should ensure human rights are better protected by this transfer. For a long time, and until human rights protection was ensured at a sufficient level within the European legal order, this was a very important issue in the European Union; Germany, for instance, has a reference to the protection of fundamental rights in its constitutional clause on the transfer of sovereignty to the European Union.(190) According to the principle proposed here, transfers of sovereignty might not only be limited by human rights, but might also be required to ensure their better protection. It might well be, for instance, that the transfer of a particular competence to the EU might protect a national minority’s interests much better than national decisions,(191) thus putting pressure on national authorities to improve the situation at the national level or else to transfer the competence to the European level.(192)


15

Secondly, in the case where a sovereign political entity neglects its human rights obligations, a humanitarian intervention may be called on human rights grounds and hence on sovereignty grounds. Indeed, the sovereignty of a ‘failed’ sovereign(193) requires that it seek ways of ensuring its duties and this may encompass accepting or even calling for an external intervention.(194) It is more complex to determine whether there is a right of the population, and respectively an obligation on the part of others to such an external intervention. It is difficult, however, to see how a sovereign entity could be held to accept external intervention aiming at re-establishing its sovereignty on grounds of its very own sovereignty, while this sovereign entity could be exempted from a duty to intervene outside of its own frontiers or competences when it could protect those very rights in other sovereign entities much better than the direct sovereign authorities themselves.(195)

3.3. Sovereignty qua a-criterial conceptto contents list

The third condition for sovereignty to be identified with an essentially contestable concept is its a-criterial nature, that is to say the absence of immutable minimal criteria of correct application. The concept of sovereignty has no immutable core criteria that should be given for there to be a sovereign; all its criteria of application can be disputed.(196) Disagreement over sovereignty is not limited to conflict over its periphery and applications, since disagreement on its core criteria cannot usually be blamed on a misunderstanding or conceptual confusion.

Of course, disagreement over contestable concepts like sovereignty needs to start on some common ground, but this shared starting point need not be constituted by core criteria;(197) parties can start by sharing paradigms which they can then progressively amend until they have reached new conceptions of the same concept.(198) For instance, control over one’s territory(199) and the principle of non-intervention(200) were for a long time the paradigms of state sovereignty; they have now gradually been abandoned and replaced by more substantive paradigms like the protection of human rights.(201) This constant renewal of paradigms explains how the concept of sovereignty can both be the starting point and the outcome of political debates. Sovereignty enables us to identify what characterizes a common phenomenon, while at the same time allowing for the identification to be questioned and reassessed thus renewing paradigms in the course of discussion.(202)

3.4. Implications of the contestability of sovereigntyto contents list

Although essentially contestable concepts like the concept of sovereignty generate much contestation and complexity, their presence and discussion should be encouraged. This is not an uncontroversial position to take;(203) some authors have been very critical of the advantages of holding on to the concept of sovereignty(204) and Stephen Krasner has made this position famous by referring to sovereignty talk as ‘organised hypocrisy’(205).

It is important to understand that contestability, rather than impoverishing debates, is likely instead to enrich intellectual life and promote tolerance within it.(206) Like other essentially contestable concepts, sovereignty’s centrality in political debates increases its contestability,(207) but it is its very contestability that makes it a central and indispensable element of debates over the best allocation of power.(208) In fact, disagreement and conflict are constitutive elements of those concepts, hence the idea of sovereignty in conflict.(209)

 

16

As a consequence, and despite chaotic appearances, it is vital for political and legal discourse as well as the development of sovereignty that debates about it not be censored. It is precisely because sovereignty is a contestable concept that it is important to discuss it rather than set it aside on grounds of indeterminacy.(210) It is through the plurality of conceptions it can give rise to that the concept of sovereignty can play its crucial political role in a changing world; it can both adapt itself to a new reality and stimulate further debate on a better allocation of power.

4. The future of sovereignty in Europe to contents list

4.1. General

These contentions about the implications of the contestability of sovereignty apply with a particular urgency to the European context(211) where the question of sovereignty has triggered heavy controversies for the past fifteen years.(212) This is hardly surprising given that, in fifty years, the European economic integration project has progressively turned into a political and legal construction whose nature is still indeterminate and unprecedented in political and legal history; different degrees of cooperation and overlapping competences between Member States and the European Union, that do not correspond to any of the known political categories, are now in place within the same territory and within the same political and legal community. The Union is neither an ordinary international organization or confederation of sovereign states, given its independent decision powers and direct relationship to its subjects(213) nor a federal and sovereign super-state given the absence of transfer of the Member States’ traditional attributes to the Union(214). Similarly, on a more legal level, the European legal order is autonomous and amounts to more than an international treaty subordinated to national law, but it is not a state-like unified legal order that integrates national legal orders in a hierarchical way. Somewhere in between lies the Union qua sui generis post-national and polycentered albeit sovereign political and legal construction whose impact on Member States’ retained sovereignty is still to be assessed.

Both the Union and the Member States have adopted very clear positions on the issue of the supremacy of European law, but their conceptions do not correspond to each other; each of them regards its own authority as absolute, original and supreme and thus as having the Kompetenz Kompetenz.(215) Hence the frequency and degree of constitutional conflicts encountered in the EU in the past fifteen years.(216) Neither the Treaties nor European practice entail a precise division of powers and this trend has not been reversed by the Draft Constitutional Treaty despite important clarifications and an express guarantee of the previously unwritten principle of supremacy of European law in Art. I-10(217) . In other words, the constitutional pluralism which characterizes the European legal order lato sensu seems difficult to reconcile with traditional conceptions of unitary sovereignty. This does not mean, however, that sovereignty is lost in Europe nor that we have moved beyond sovereignty and need to redefine it. All it reveals is that paradigms of sovereignty have changed and that new conceptions have emerged that conflict with prior ones, thus confirming the essentially contestable nature of the concept of sovereignty.

There are many implications to the contestability of sovereignty in Europe. Most importantly, it allows all sides of the debate to hold on to their conceptions of sovereignty and of its relationship to their respective legal orders. Besides, thanks to the perpetuation of the concept of sovereignty and of the debates it generates, progress can be made without incurring a breach with the past. This state of collective uncertainty may therefore be regarded as intentional or at least beneficial in the European context. Some authors, like Ian Ward or Catherine Richmond, actually emphasize the importance of preserving the European identity crisis through perpetuating the contestability of the concept of sovereignty.(218)


17

4.2. Current conceptions of sovereigntyto contents list

So far, and very schematically, there have been three major alternative conceptions of sovereignty in Europe.

To start with, some authors still propound an absolute and unitary conception of sovereignty that does not really fit the pluralist European legal reality. According to them, sovereignty on specific matters must belong either to Member States or to the EU, but cannot belong to both, hence the conflicting narratives one encounters on either side of the debate(219) and the ‘revolt or revolution’ nexus.(220) Unitary accounts of sovereignty in the EU can be divided into two main groups. The first group encompasses mostly national intergovernmentalists(221) , who understand national constitutions as the ultimate legal rule in the EU, or European supranationalists(222) , who on the contrary see national constitutions as subordinated to the European legal order. As to the second group, it encompasses very different authors like the latest Neil MacCormick(223) or Ingolf Pernice(224) who share the common view that although European political and legal reality is pluralistic and calls for a more flexible account of sovereignty, sovereignty remains a unitary phenomenon according to which ultimate decision-making authority ought to be exercized in a one-dimensional way whether at the European or international level.(225) The difficulty with these approaches is, to quote Walker, ‘the myopic partiality of simple unitary positions in the face of substantial evidence of growing constitutional plurality’, as well as the doubtful ‘capacity even of the more complex and sophisticated unitarianism of multi-level constitutionalism and its ilk to sustain robust pluralist political premises(226)’. It is important to emphasize that, contrary to what some have argued, the failure of the unitary model of sovereignty will not be redeemed by the European constitutional exercize. It is possible to reconcile the existence of a Constitutional Treaty and the consolidation of the constitutional legitimacy of the European polity, on the one hand, with constitutional pluralism and the co-existence of both European and national sovereignty, on the other.(227)

In response to the failure of the unitary sovereignty model in the EU, a second group of conceptions of sovereignty has emerged. The idea of disaggregation and reaggregation of sovereignty has been brought forward to grasp the poly-centred dimension of sovereignty in Europe. The problem with this kind of pooled or shared sovereignty, however, is that by being everywhere, it seems that it is nowhere particularly important.(228) As Walker argues, pooled sovereignty sits ‘uneasily with the sense of sovereignty as a unifying and self-identifying claim made on behalf of the polity(229)’. Although many authors have defended a pooled or divided conception of sovereignty at one stage or another from the early 1970s to the early 1990s,(230) most seem to have moved away from it, either to go back to a unitary model of sovereignty or to move towards a resolutely post-sovereign stance.

A third approach dispenses entirely with the concept of sovereignty. After all, the tyranny of statist concepts is a well-known fact(231) and there is no reason why the organization of a post-national polity like the EU should follow the same rules as national polities.(232) The difficulty with the early MacCormick’s and others’ claims to post-sovereignty, however, lies in their blindness to the essential epistemic and normative role of sovereignty,(233) whether it is attached to states or other sub-national or post-national political entities. Claims to ultimate authority and finalité are regularly made by national and EU authorities, be it by the judiciary or other authorities and be it in the form of claims to sovereignty or of claims to identity and self-determination(234) . These claims arise in very diverse regulatory fields such as those of nationality and citizenship acquisition,(235) monetary regulation(236) or fundamental rights.(237) Sovereignty is too deeply entrenched in our legal and political language and too prevalent in public debate to be ignored as an object of serious theoretical reflection.(238)


18

4.3. Cooperative sovereignty in Europe to contents list

If it is true that our conceptions of sovereignty in Europe should not map unitary conceptions of sovereignty too closely,(239) this need not imply a complete rejection but only a more adequate translation of the concept in the European post-national context. It is possible to opt for a fourth conception that fits current legal paradigms in Europe better and in particular its constitutional pluralism(240). Sovereignty in Europe could very well be conceived as both ultimate and pluralistic along the lines of the cooperative model of sovereignty mentioned before.(241)

In propounding this approach to sovereignty in Europe, we would retreat from the assumptions of post-sovereignty without giving in to the rigidity of the unitary approach or the false promises of pooled sovereignty. On this model, both national and European authorities retain their sovereignty but in having to be sovereign together, they cannot escape a certain degree of competition, emulation and cooperation which characterizes sovereignty in a pluralistic constitutional order, thus paradoxically fortifying rather than diminishing their individual sovereignties.(242) This conception of sovereignty corresponds to the close cooperation and prevention of conflicts among authorities that one may observe in practice and through which the European legal order was gradually constructed from ‘bottom up’ rather than ‘top-down’.(243) European law should therefore be understood as the product of discourse and cooperation among the actors of a broad European legal community which encompasses both the European legal community stricto sensu and national legal communities.(244) On this account, the exercize of sovereignty becomes reflexive and dynamic as it implies a search for the best allocation of power in each case, thus putting into question and potentially improving others’ exercize of sovereignty as well as one’s own. According to Walker’s similar conception of late sovereignty,

‘The interrogative gaze of sovereign authorities may no longer be exclusively directed outwards towards competing or putative sovereign orders, but, in response to these competing claims, and also to the self-organising and self-regulatory claims of communities of practice and interest which do not define themselves as multi-functional polities, may also turn inwards.’ (245)

4.4. The risks and advantages of cooperative sovereigntyto contents list

4.4.1. Erosion and duties of cooperative sovereignty

Even though there are numerous advantages to defending this form of pluralist and cooperative sovereignty, risks of erosion of sovereignty through reflexivity and questioning should not be underestimated in the European Union. Besides the factual and sociological tendency one can observe towards sovereignty’s constructive development through pluralism and conflict(246), the risks of erosion may also be defeated by a normative argument. Cooperative sovereignty implies the emergence of mutual duties of adjustment and cooperation on the part of national and European judicial authorities active in the European legal order. As I have argued elsewhere, the dynamic and reflexive nature of cooperative sovereignty actually matches the existence of independent duties of coherence or integrity which go further than mere requirements of dialogue and mutual respect.(247) According to the European integrity principle, all national and European authorities should make sure their decisions are consistent in principle with the past decisions of other European and national authorities which create and implement the law of a complex but single European legal order.


19

Only so can the European political and legal community gain true authority and legitimacy in the eyes of the European citizens to whom all these decisions apply. Miguel Poiares Maduro derives similar ‘harmonic principles of contrapunctual law’ from his conception of competitive sovereignty(248) and argues that

‘[European and national] authorities’ decisions should not be seen as separate interpretations and applications of European law, but as decisions to be integrated in a system of law requiring compatibility and coherence’.(249)

These cooperative duties are necessary in a pluralist legal order; they are the limits to cooperative sovereignty necessary to ensure the cooperative nature of sovereignty or ‘the limits to pluralism necessary to allow the largest extent of pluralism possible(250)’. This implies that if either national or European authorities do not fulfil their obligations towards the others, the latter should be discharged from its reciprocal obligations.(251) This demonstrates how, as I have claimed elsewhere, coherence could become the virtue of Europeans’ integrated sovereignty, i.e. the virtue of a community which wants to integrate itself without, however, renouncing its diversity and hence its pluralism.(252) This idea is perfectly captured by Richard Bellamy’s account of mixed sovereignty:

‘[…] unity is constructed via a dialogue amongst a plurality, with the one being continually challenged, renegotiated and reconstructed as the other evolves and becomes more diverse.’(253)

It is important to understand that these duties of coherence and cooperation are duties of political morality rather than legal or institutionalized duties. Cooperative sovereignty captures a political reality in which distinct political and legal sovereigns overlap in the same community and territory, thus undermining the idea of a supreme and unifying legal framework of cooperation.(254) Contrary to what MacCormick argues when he opposes radical pluralism to his own soft or monist type of pluralism, however, this does not leave us with only plain politics and negotiation.(255) The commonality of population and territory implies, on the contrary, a joint moral responsibility on the part of all political and legal authorities.(256) And this responsibility encompasses cooperative duties of tolerance, dialogue and coherence among others.(257)

4.4.2. Polity legitimacy and benefits of cooperative sovereigntyto contents list

Far from being a difficulty, potential sovereignty conflicts implied by the proposed conception of cooperative sovereignty could constitute an advantage in practice. This is because cooperative sovereignty provides the normative framework for the development of a dynamic and reflexive form of constitutionalism in Europe(258) and hence for the constitutional legitimation of the European polity.(259) Even if the framework of sovereignty does not exhaust the search for post-national political values and needs to be complemented by the promotion of constitutional values such as political discourse and citizenship in Europe, sovereignty anchors constitutional pluralism and is the inescapable precondition of post-national polity formation.(260) More precisely, the cooperative model of sovereignty presents three advantages for the emerging legitimacy of the European Union.

 
 
 
 
 

20

4.4.2.1. Adjudication and taming constitutional conflicts

Cooperative sovereignty constitutes an inspiring solution for all those who are concerned about the resolution of constitutional conflicts in Europe and the way the different jurisdictions control each other’s laws’ constitutionality.(261) Different ways to settle these conflicts have been brought forward over the past few years and they include dialogue(262) or international/supra-European modes of legal settlement.(263)

Duties of cooperative sovereignty and in particular duties of coherence lead authorities beyond mere requirements of judicial dialogue and mutual respect(264) , towards a true European cooperative constitutional control.(265) It follows from what has been said about cooperative sovereignty in the European Union that constitutionality controls, either on the European or the national sides, should be seen as cooperative and reflexive.(266) Sovereignty qua question implies that sovereign authorities constantly reflect on the justification of their sovereignty by comparison to that of others over the same population and territory. National and European jurisdictions cannot afford to work separately and with no regard whatsoever for the other side’s constitutional rules.(267) As a consequence, in case of constitutional conflict, European and national authorities should question the grounds for their sovereignty on the issue at stake and be ready to contest them if required.

According to this integrity-based model of constitutional control, adjudication in Europe could be much more respectful of other authorities’ laws and decisions and coherent than it is usually said to be. Most principles and values that are protected on each side are common to all European constitutional instruments and this even more so now that the European Charter of Fundamental Rights is about to become binding through entrenchment in the European Constitutional Treaty. Thus, disagreement about the best way to realize these common constitutional rights and principles enhances the need for cooperation and coherence in protecting them in each jurisdiction. This may be done mainly through a form of mutual interpretation and justification, whether this occurs through a preliminary ruling or not. This approach may actually be confirmed by the recent willingness to cooperate on the part of national courts and the ECJ.(268) In fact, the European Constitutional Treaty is about to reinforce and even extend this framework of cooperation among sovereign authorities by expressly stating the supremacy clause,(269) clarifying jurisdictional boundaries and enhancing human rights guarantees and democratic procedures.(270) Fewer constitutional conflicts should therefore arise in the future, and when they do, it will be on a more informed basis and they should hence become more constructive.

Following the considerations I mentioned earlier about the moral and non-legal nature of cooperative duties, it should be clear why the proposed model of cooperative constitutional control is not to be translated legally or institutionalized in any way. Establishing rules of priority among European and national constitutional norms in case of conflict, along the lines proposed by Mattias Kumm and Victor Ferreres-Comella,(271) is a competence that cannot belong exclusively either to national constitutional law or to European constitutional law. Such rules would undermine the trust and responsibility that characterize the cooperative relationship between ultimate national and European authorities. Besides, it is an element inherent to what I referred to as the contestability of the sovereignty threshold that conflicts of sovereignty might occur on any matter of constitutional importance, thus excluding the possibility of determining those matters in advance or accordingly of fixing them in a common legal rule. As Maduro argues, it is important to leave the Kompetenz-Kompetenz issue open in the joint and cooperative enterprise of European constitutionalism.(272)

 
 

21

4.4.2.2. Legislation and enhancing trans-European democratic standards

Another key illustration of the significance of cooperative sovereignty for polity-legitimacy in Europe lies in the competition and cooperation that should prevail among democratic authorities.(273) Since democratic rule is one of the values protected by sovereignty, the exercize of sovereignty qua question implies looking for the best level of decision to endow those affected by that decision with the strongest voice and hearing in Europe.(274)

This is particularly important in the context of the ‘democratic deficit’ accusations. One of the central legitimacy deficits in the EU is said to be the democratic deficit due very schematically to the insufficient and at best distant connection between European decisions and popular participation. Rather than follow the misguided approach that aims at establishing state-like and centralized democracy at EU level,(275) potentially based on a unified and homogeneous demos, the democratic specificity of the European political arrangement should be seen to lie in the interaction and cooperation among national and European democratic institutions and hence among different demoi in Europe.(276) Instead of focusing only on the horizontal division of labour in European institutions, the democratic agenda should also be realized in the vertical division of competences in the European political community in general. European democracy can, in other words, be one of the outcomes of the cooperative and trans-European exercize of popular sovereignty.(277) A differentiated but cooperative exercize of national popular sovereignty might therefore lead to an increase in democratic legitimacy, both at the national and European levels.(278)

Of course, more work remains to be done to ensure the cooperation among national and European democratic authorities in practice. One may mention the necessity to develop a trans-European public sphere and to stimulate trans-European political debates through the promotion of pan-European political parties. An area where cooperative sovereignty could already be said to provide the means to develop a strong trans-European democracy is European inter-parliamentary cooperation. The importance of dialogue between parliaments throughout Europe has been emphasized a lot in recent years.(279) A Protocol to the Draft Constitutional Treaty actually establishes a series of measures to strengthen the involvement of national parliaments in EU decision-making which include, for instance, a duty to inform national parliaments, a common code of conduct and an early-warning mechanism in case of non-compliance with the principle of subsidiarity. Besides the advantages of the creation of a European parliamentary public sphere,(280) one could argue that, once information has been exchanged, the legislative outcome, be it national or European, should be affected as a result of integrity duties and be required to speak with a Euro-coherent voice.(281) The benefits of European inter-parliamentary cooperation could be measured in terms of both national and European democratic legitimacy. Transnational legislative dialogue and mutual comparison could add onto national standards of democratic legitimacy; they could contribute to enhancing the democratic quality of national legislation by introducing a form of double representation of the European demoi and hence of double check on national legislation. Moreover, national decisions in Europe are increasingly affected by European, but also by other national decisions in which they have no democratic representation.(282) The application of the principle of European integrity to the European Parliament could help alleviating the democratic deficit that plagues the European Parliament’s legislation.(283)

 
 
 
 
 

22

4.4.2.3. Constitutionalism and reinforcing European constitutional legitimacy

Cooperative sovereignty reinforces European constitutionalism qua process,(284) i.e. the process of constitutionalization of the European Union which started fifty years ago and the outcome of which is currently being reorganized.(285) This process is a cross-disciplinary and cross-institutional one, as it implies different types of national and European authorities(286) in different legal fields that have a constitutional function in a broad sense of the term.(287) In these conditions, the duties of European cooperative sovereignty constitute a form of European constitutional discipline. All national and European authorities are reminded by their responsibilities of sovereignty that they are contributing to the gradual constitution or even to the re-constitution of Europe. They therefore have to test their decisions for coherence against other European and national constitutional standards before taking them.(288) This notion of competitive constitutionalism corresponds to Maduro’s conception of competitive sovereignty:

‘On the one hand, European constitutionalism promotes inclusiveness in national constitutionalism both from an external and internal perspective. […] On the other hand, national constitutionalism also serves as a guarantee against the possible concentrations and abuses of power from European constitutionalism and, at the same time, requires the latter to constantly improve its constitutional standards in light of the challenges and requirements imposed on it by national constitutions.’(289)

Of course, this form of constitutional discipline should not be interpreted as a way to disavow the Draft Constitutional Treaty, nor the outcomes of the 2004 IGC. It corresponds more closely, however, to the nature of the European community and the flexible way in which it has gradually constituted itself in fifty years of integration. The duties implied by cooperative sovereignty ensure a flexible and non-hierarchical cooperation between European constitutionalism and national constitutions.(290) In respecting duties of cooperative sovereignty, European constitutionalism qua process promotes the very ideals of respect and tolerance Joseph Weiler associates with the European constitution.(291) Despite its numerous other advantages,(292) a formal European Constitution should not disrupt this flexible and pluralist constitutional process and take the risk of replacing it with a rigid constitutional order. To prevent this, European institutions should actively foster the cooperative attitude and deliberation(293) among national and European constitutional authorities that was triggered by the European ‘constitutional moment’.(294)

Conclusionto contents list

Neither post-sovereignty, nor absolute and indivisible sovereignty in the Hobbesian sense, tomorrow’s sovereignty is both identical and different to yesterday’s. As it is the reasoned outcome of constant conflict and periodical changes of paradigms, sovereignty is neither the simple reflection of the new European and international reality nor the application of a pre-established concept whose criteria are immutable and risk corseting the post-national order. Both open and closed, the concept of sovereignty frames and stimulates debates that go deep into the heart of what should be the best allocation of power both in Europe and in the global order. As an essentially contestable concept, sovereignty is at once a state of affairs, a question pertaining to the nature and justification of that state of affairs and a justification of it. The correct use of the concept of sovereignty and hence the correct exercize of authority it implies consists therefore in constantly reflecting and contesting one’s use of the concept and hence one’s exercize of sovereignty.


23

As such, the question-concept or reflexive concept of sovereignty can be described as cooperative in the post-national constellation where sovereign entities overlap in their claims to sovereignty over the same territory and population. Read together with the principle of subsidiarity, cooperative sovereignty implies allocating competences to those authorities that are best placed to ensure the protection of shared sovereign values and principles. Sovereignty’s use is both dynamic and reflexive and implies mutual learning and progress in the protection of the values it encompasses, such as the values of democracy and fundamental rights.

In the European context, cooperative sovereignty provides the normative framework for the development of a dynamic and reflexive form of constitutionalism and hence of constitutional legitimation of the European polity. It reconciles national and European conflicting claims of sovereignty and the epistemological and normative resilience of sovereignty in the European Union, on the one hand, with constitutional pluralism and the coexistence of many different legal orders within the same territory and political community, on the other. Through its duties of cooperation and coherence, cooperative sovereignty countervails the risks of erosion implied by legal pluralism, while also enhancing the legitimacy of the European polity. This can be observed in the context of difficult issues such as adjudication and constitutional conflicts, legislation and democratic deficits and, finally, constitutionalism and the European constitutional moment. In a nutshell, cooperative sovereignty places conflicts of sovereignty at the centre of European politics, as both an incentive and a means of integration by way of comparison and self-reflexivity.


Referencesto contents list

Aalberts T. 2004, The Future of Sovereignty in Multilevel Governance Europe – A Constructivist Reading, 42:1 Journal of Common Market Studies 23.

Allot P. 1999, The Concept of International Law, 10 European Journal of International Law 31.

Annan K. 1999, The Question of Intervention, Statements by the Secretary General, 6.

Arendt H. 1973, On Revolution, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Aziz M. 2003, Sovereignty über Alles: (Re)configuring the German Legal Order, in N. Walker (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 12.

Bankowski Z. 1977, Subsidiarity, Sovereignty and Self, in Norr/Oppermann (eds), Subsidiarität: Idee und Wirklichkeit. Zur Reichweite eines Prinzips in Deutschland und Europa, Frankfurt: JCB Mohr, 23.

Bankowski/Christodoulidis 2000, The European Union as an Essentially Contested Project, in Bankowski/Scott (eds), The European Union and its Legal Order, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17.

Barber N. 2000, Sovereignty Re-examined: The Courts, Parliament and Statutes, 21 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 130.

Bartelson J. 1995, A Genealogy of Sovereignty, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bellamy R. 2003, Sovereignty, Post-Sovereignty and Pre-Sovereignty: The Three Models of the State, Democracy and Rights within the EU, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Bellamy/Castiglione 1997, Building the Union: the nature of sovereignty in the political architecture of Europe, 16 Law and Philosophy 91.

Bellamy/Castiglione 2004, Normative Theory and the European Union: Legitimising the Euro-polity and its Regime, in Tragardh L. (ed.), After National Democracy: Rights, Law and Power in the New Europe, Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Bermann G. 1994, Taking Subsidiarity Seriously: Federalism in the European Community and the United States, 94 Columbia Law Review 331.

Besson S. 2000, Conflits constitutionnels en Europe – une lecture de l’Affaire Kreil c. République fédérale d’Allemagne, 5 Pratique Juridique Actuelle 563.

Besson S. 2003a, La souveraineté coopérative en Europe, in Balmelli T. (ed.), La Suisse saisie par l’Europe, Fribourg: Editions Interuniversitaires Suisses, 5.

Besson S. 2003b, Post-souveraineté ou simple changement de paradigmes? Variations sur un concept essentiellement contestable, in Balmelli/Borghi/Hildbrand (eds), La souveraineté au XXIème siècle, Fribourg: Editions Interuniversitaires Suisses, 7.

Besson S. 2003c, Human Rights, Institutional Duties and Cosmopolitan Responsibilities, Review of T. Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Oxford: Blackwell 2002, 23:3 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 507.

Besson, S. 2004a, From Integration to Integrity: Should European Law Speak With Just One Voice?, 10:3 European Law Journal 257.

Besson S. 2004b, The Taming of Sovereignty, Review of N. Walker’s Sovereignty in Transition, 2:3 International Journal of Constitutional Law forthcoming.

Besson S. 2005, The Morality of Conflict. Reasonable Disagreement and the Law, Hart Publishing: Oxford.

Biersteker/Weber (eds) 1996, State Sovereignty as Social Construction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bleckmann A. 1994, Article 2 (1), in Simma B. (ed.), The Charter of the United Nations – A commentary, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Blichner L.C. 2000, Interparliamentary discourse and the quest for legitimacy, in Eriksen/Fossum (eds), Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation, London: Routledge, 140.

Blichner/Sangolt 1994, The Concept of Subsidiarity and the Debate on European Cooperation: Pitfalls and Possibilities, 7:3 Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 284.

Bodin J. 1993, Les six livres de la République, Paris: Librairie Générale Française.

von Bogdandy A. 2000, The European Union as a Supranational Federation: A Conceptual Attempt in the light of the Amsterdam Treaty, 6 Columbia Journal of European Law 27.

Bond M. 1997, The European Parliament in the 1990s, 3:2 The Journal of Legislative Studies 1.

Brownlie I. 1979, Principles of Public International Law, 3rd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bull H. 1966, The Grotian Conception of International Society, in Butterfield/Wight (eds), Diplomatic Investigations, London: Sage.

De Burca G. 1999, Reappraising Sovereignty’s Significance After Amsterdam, 7/99 Harvard Jean Monnet Working Paper 14.

De Burca G. 2003, Sovereignty and the Supremacy Doctrine of the European Court of Justice, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 19.

Chalmers D. 1997, Judicial Preferences and the Community Legal Order, 60 Modern Law Review 164.

Cohen/Sabel 2003, Sovereignty and Solidarity: EU and US, in Zeitlin/Trubek (eds), Governing Work and Welfare in a New Economy: European and American Experiments, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Ch. 13.

Connolly W. 1983, The Terms of Political Discourse, 2nd edn, Oxford: Robertson.

Craig P. 2001, Constitutions, Constitutionalism and the European Union, 7 European Law Journal 125.

Curtin D. 1997, Postnational Democracy: The European Union in Search of a Political Philosophy, La Haye: Kluwer Law International.

Dennert J. 1964, Ursprung und Begriff der Souveränität, Stuttgart: G. Fischer.

Douglas Scott S. 2002, The Constitutional Law of the European Union, London: Maxwell.

Dworkin R. 1991, Law’s Empire, London: Fontana Press.

Dworkin R. 2004, Hart’s Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy, 24:1 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1.

Eleftheriadis P. 1996, Aspects of European Constitutionalism, 21 European Law Review 32.

Eleftheriadis P. 1998, Begging the Constitutional Question, 36 Journal of Common Market Studies 255.

Emiliou N. 1992, Subsidiarity: An Effective Barrier Against ‘The Enterprises of Ambition’, European Law Review 383.

Eriksen/Fossum 2001, Democracy through strong publics in the European Union?, ARENA Working Paper 01/16. <http://www.arena.uio.no/publications/wp01_16.htm>

Ermacora F. 1966, Die vierte Gewalt: eine regional-supranationale Gewalt zum Schutze der Menschenrechte, in Liber Amicorum Gerhard Leibholz, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 673.

Esher J. 1999, Der kooperative Nationalstaat im Zeitalter der Globalisierung, in Döring D. (ed.), Sozialstaat in der Globalisierung, Francfort: JCB Mohr, 117.

Estella A. 2002, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and Its Critiques, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Falk R. 1990, Evasions of Sovereignty, in Walker/Mendlevitz (eds), Contending Sovereignties: Redefining Political Community, Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 61.

Falk R. 1997, The Grotian Moment, 13 International Insights 3.

Falk R. 1999, Predatory Globalization: A Critique, Cambridge: Polity.

Falk R. 2001, Sovereignty, in The Oxford Companion to Politcs in the World, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Farr J. 1989, Understanding conceptual change politically, in Ball/Farr/Hanson (eds), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 24.

Follesdal A. 1998, Subsidiarity, 6:2 Journal of Political Philosophy 231.

Follesdal A. 2000, Subsidiarity and Democratic Deliberation, in Eriksen/Fossum (eds), Democracy in the European Union – Integration through Deliberation, London: Routledge, 85.

Freeden M. 2003, Ideology, A very short introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gallie W.B. 1956, Essentially contested concepts, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56, 167.

Gray J. 1977, On the contestability of social and political concepts, 5 Political Theory 331.

Gray J. 1978, On Liberty, Liberalism and Essential Contestability, 8 British Journal of Political Science 385.

Grewe/Ruiz Fabri 1992, Le Conseil constitutionnel et l’intégration européenne, Revue universelle des droits de l’homme 277.

Grimm D. 1995, Does Europe Need a Constitution?, 1 European Law Journal 282.

Grotius H. 1913, De Iure Belli ac Pacis, in Scott J.B. (ed.), Classics of International Law, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Guggenheim P. 1968, La souveraineté dans l’histoire du droit des gens. De Vitoria à Vattel, in Mélanges Juraj Andrassy, The Hague: Kluwer International, 111.

Habermas, J. 1998, Die Postnationale Konstellation, Francfort: Suhrkamp.

Habermas J. 2001, The postnational constellation and the future of democracy, in Habermas J. (ed.), The Postnational Constellation – Political Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 58.

Häberle P. 1967, Zur gegenwärtigen Diskussion um das Problem der Souveränität, 92 Archiv für öffentliches Recht 282.

Hampshire S. 1959, Thought and Action, London: Chatto and Windus.

Henkel C. 2002, The Allocation of Powers in the European Union: A Closer Look at the Principle of Subsidiarity, 20 Berkeley Journal of International Law 359.

Hinsley F.H. 1986, Sovereignty, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hobbes T. 1999, in Tuck R. (ed.), Leviathan, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hobe S. 1997, Statehood at the end of the 20th Century – The Model of the ‘Open State’: A German Perspective, 2 Austrian Review of International and European Law 127.

Hoffman J. 1997, Blind Alleys: Can we define Sovereignty ?, 17 Politics 53.

Howarth D. 1995, Discourse Theory, in Marsh/Stoker (eds), Theory and Methods in Political Science, Basingstoke: Macmillan.

Huber M. 1929, Palmas-Fall, 1:II Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 3.

Hurley S. 1989, Natural Reasons, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Jackson R. 1990, Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International Relations and the Third World, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jackson R. 1997, The Grotian Moment in World Jurisprudence, 13 International Insights 35.

Jackson R. 1999a, Introduction: Sovereignty at the Millenium, 47 Political Studies 423.

Jackson R. 1999b, Sovereignty in World Politics: A Glance at the Conceptual and Historical Landscape, 47 Political Studies 431.

James A. 1986, Sovereign Statehood: the Basis of International Society, London: Allen & Unwin.

James A. 1999, The Practice of Sovereign Statehood in Contemporary International Society, 47 Political Studies 457.

Jessurun D’Oliveira 1999, Nationality and the European Union after Amsterdam, in O’Keeffe/Twomey (eds), Legal Issues of the Amsterdam Treaty, Hart Publishing: Oxford.

Joerges C. 2002, ‘Deliberative Supranationalism’ – Two Defences, 8 European Law Journal 133.

Jones J. 1997, The Committee of the Regions, Subsidiarity and a Warning, 22 European Law Review 312.

Kaufmann P. 1999, Integrierte Staatlichkeit als Staatsstrukturprinzip, 54 Juristen Zeitung 814.

Keating M. 2001, Plurinational Democracy: Stateless nations in a Post-Sovereignty Era, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Keating M. 2002, Europe’s Changing Landscape: Territorial Restructuring and New Forms of Government, in Beaumont/Lyons/Walker (eds), Convergence and Divergence in European Public Law, Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Kelsen H. 1926, Les rapports de système entre le droit interne et le droit international public, Annuaire de droit international 1926/IV.

Kelsen H. 1928, Das Problem der Souveränität, 2nd edn, Tübingen: Mohr.

Kelsen H. 1942, Law and Peace in International Relations: The Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures, Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Kelsen H. 1961, The General Theory of the Law and the State, New York: Russell & Russell.

Keohane R. 2003, Ironies of Sovereignty: The European Union and the United States, (2002) 40:4 Journal of Common Market Studies 743, republished in Weiler/Begg/Peterson (eds), Integration in an Expanding European Union, Reassessing the Fundamentals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kirchhof P. 1998, Die Gewaltenbalance zwischen staatlichen und europäischen Organen, 53 Juristen Zeitung 940.

Koskonniemi M. 1991, The Future of Statehood, 32:2 Harvard International Law Journal 397.

Kostakopoulou D. 2002, Floating Sovereignty: A Pathology or a Necessary Means of State Evolution ?, 22 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 135.

Krasner S. 1988, Sovereignty: an institutional perspective, 21 Comparative Political Studies 66.

Krasner S. 1993, Westphalia and All That, in Goldstein/Keohane (eds), Ideas and Foreign Policy, Beliefs, Institutions and Political Change, London: Cornell University Press, 235.

Krasner S. 1999, Sovereignty: Organised Hypocrisy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Kumm M. 1999, Who is the final arbiter of constitutionality in Europe? Three conceptions of the relationship between the German Federal Constitutional Court and the European Court of Justice, 36 Common Market Law Review 351.

Kumm M. 2004a, Constitutionalizing Subsidiarity in Integrated Markets, in Maduro/Halberstam (eds), The Constitutional Challenge in Europe and America: People, Power, and Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kumm M. 2004b, The Jurisprudence of Constitutional Conflict. Reconceiving the Relationship between the Law of the European Union and Its Member States, Jean Monnet Working Paper forthcoming.

Kumm/Ferreres-Comella 2004, The Future of Constitutional Conflict in the European Union: Constitutional Supremacy after the Constitutional Treaty, 2:3 International Journal of Constitutional Law forthcoming.

Laski H.J. 1917, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Laski H.J. 1941, A Grammar of Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lecheler H. 1992, Das Subsidiaritätsprinzip, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

Lee S. 1997, A Puzzle of Sovereignty, 27 Californian Western International Law Journal 241.

Lenaerts K. 1990, Constitutionalism and the Many Faces of Federalism, 28 American Journal of Comparative Law 205.

Lindahl H. 1997, Sovereignty and Symbolization, 27 Rechtstheorie 3.

Lindahl H. 2002, Sovereignty and Representation in the EU, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 4.

Loughlin M. 2003, Ten Tenets of Sovereignty, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 3.

MacCormick N. 1993, Beyond the Sovereign State, 56 Modern Law Review 1.

MacCormick N. 1995a, Sovereignty, Democracy and Subsidiarity, in Bellamy/Castiglione (eds), Democracy and Constitutional Culture in the Union of Europe, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

MacCormick N. 1995b, The Maastricht- Urteil: Sovereignty Now, 1:3 European Law Journal 255.

MacCormick N. 1996, Liberalism, Nationalism and the Post-sovereign State, 44 Political Studies 553.

MacCormick N. 1997, Democracy, Subsidiarity and Citizenship in the European Commonwealth, 16:4 Law and Philosophy 331.

MacCormick N. 1998, Risking Constitutional Collision in Europe?, 18 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 517.

MacCormick N. 1999, Questioning Sovereignty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

MacIntyre A. 1973, The Essential Contestability of Some Social Concepts, 84 Ethics 1.

Maduro Poiares M. 2002, Where to look for legitimacy?, in Eriksen/Fossum/Menendez, Constitution Making and Democratic Legitimacy, ARENA Report No 5/2002.

Maduro Poiares M. 2003, Contrapunctual Law: Europe’s Constitutional Pluralism in Action, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 21.

Magnette P. 2000, L’Europe, l' Etat et la Démocratie, Bruxelles: Editions Complexe.

Mancini F. 1989, The Making of a Constitution for Europe, 26 Common Market Law Review 5933.

Mancini F. 1998, Europe: the Case for Statehood, 4 European Law Journal 29.

Marquardt P. 1994, Subsidiarity and Sovereignty in the European Union, 18 Fordham International Law Journal 616.

Mayall J. 1999, Sovereignty, Nationalism and Self-Determination, 47 Political Studies 474.

Mény Y. 2003, De la démocratie en Europe: Old Concepts and New Challenges, 41:1 Journal of Common Market Studies 1.

Miller J.D.B. 1981, The World of States: Connected Essays, London: Croom Helm.

Miller D. 1983, Linguistic Philosophy and Political Theory, in Miller/Siedentop (eds), The Nature of Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Miller/Ware 1996, Keeping National Parliaments Informed: The Problem of European Legislation, 2:3 The Journal of Legislative Studies 184.

Milward A.S. 1992, The European Rescue of the Nation State, London: Routledge.

Moravcsik A. 2002, Reassessing Legitimacy in the European Union, 40:4 Journal of Common Market Studies 603.

Mortelmans K. 1996, Community Law: more than a Functional Area of Law, Less than a Legal System, 1 Legal Issues of European Integration 23.

Müller J.P. 1999a, Souveränität und Menschenrechte, in Der politische Mensch und menschliche Politik, Basel: Helbing Liechtenhahn, 132.

Müller J.P. 1999b, Menschenrechtliche und demokratische Dynamik des Subsidiaritätsprinzips – Gedanken zu einem Konstitutionsprinzip der EU, in Der politische Mensch und menschliche Politik, Basel: Helbing Liechtenhahn, 167.

Müller J.P. 2002, Begriff und Wandel der Souveränität, in Die demokratische Verfassung, Zürich: NZZ Verlag, 135.

Nicolaidis K. 2003, The New Constitution as European Demoi-cracy?, The Federal Trust Constitutional Online Paper 38/03. <http://www.fedtrust.co.uk/uploads/constitution/38_03.pdf>

Olivier P. 1994, The French Constitution and the Treaty of Maastricht, 43 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 1.

Pernice I. 2002, Multilevel Constitutionalism in the European Union, 27 European Law Review 511.

Pescatore P. 1970, L’apport du droit communautaire au droit international public, Cahiers de droit européen 501.

Peterson J. 1994, Subsidiarity: A Definition to Suit any Vision?, 47 Parliamentary Affairs 116.

Pfersmann O. 2001, Etat et Souveraineté, in Favoreu L. et al. (ed.), Droit constitutionnel, 4th edn, Paris: Dalloz.

Phelan D. 1997, Revolt or Revolution: The Constitutional Boundaries of the European Community, Dublin: Round Hall.

Philpott D. 1999, Westphalia, Authority and International Society, 47 Political Studies 566.

Pogge T. 1992, Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty, 103 Ethics 48.

Preuss U. 1999, The Constitution of a European Democracy and the Role of the Nation State, 12 Ratio Juris 417.

Raz J. 1998, Two views of the nature of the theory of law: a partial comparison, 4 Legal Theory 249.

Raz J. 2001, Moral Change and Social Relativism, in Engaging Reason, On the Theory of Value and Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Reisman W.M. 1990, Sovereignty and human rights in contemporary international law, 84 American Journal of International Law 866.

Rhonheimer D. 1989, Der moderne Staat zwischen Gewaltmonopol und Rechtsbindung, Anmerkungen zum neuzeitlichen Souveränitätsbegriff, Studia Philosophica, Supplementum 13, 261.

Ricciardi M. 2001, Essential Contestability and the Claims of Analysis, in Carter/Ricciardi (eds), The Power of Freedom, Essays in Honour of Felix Oppenheim, Basingstoke: Palgrave.

Richmond C. 1997, Preserving the identity crisis: autonomy, system and sovereignty in European law, 16 Law and Philosophy 377.

Risse T. 2003, Sovereignty Puzzles, in Weiler/Begg/Peterson (eds), Integration in an Expanding European Union, Reassessing the Fundamentals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Van Roermund B. 1997, Jurisprudential Dilemmas of European Law, 16 Law and Philosophy 357.

Rousseau J.-J. 1962, Le contrat social, Paris: 10/18.

Schilling T. 1996a, The Autonomy of the Community Order- An Analysis of Possible Foundations, 37 Harvard Journal of International Law 411

Schilling T. 1996b, Rejoinder: The Autonomy of the Community Legal Order, Harvard Jean Monnet Working Paper 10/96. <http://www.jeanmonnetprogram.org/papers/96/9610.html>

Schmitt C. 1996, Politische Theologie, Vier Kapitel zur Lehre von der Souveränität, 7th edn, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot 1996.

Schmitter P.C. 1996a, If the Nation-State were to wither away in Europe, what might replace it?, in Gustavsson/Lewin (eds), The Future of the Nation State, London: Routledge, 211.

Schmitter P.C. 1996b, Imagining the Future of the Euro-Polity with the Help of New Concepts, in Marks/Scharpf/Schmitter/Streeck (eds), Governance in the European Union, London: Sage, 121.

Schreuer C. 1993, The Waning of the Sovereign State: Towards a New Paradigm for International Law ?, 4 European Journal of International Law 447.

Schwarze J. (ed.) 2000, The Birth of a European Constitutional Order: the Interaction of National and European Constitutional Law, Baden-Baden: Nomos.

Shaw J. 1999, The emergence of postnational constitutionalism in the European Union, 6 Journal of European Public Policy 579.

Shaw J. 2001, Postnational Constitutionalism in the European Union, in Christiansen/Joergensen/Wiener (eds), The Social Construction of Europe, London: Sage, 66

Shaw J. 2003a, Process, Responsibility and Inclusion in EU Constitutionalism, 9:1 European Law Journal 45.

Shaw J. 2003b, Sovereignty at the Boundaries of the Polity, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing, Ch. 20.

Shaw/Wiener 2000, The Paradox of the ‘European Polity’, in Green Cowles/Smith (eds), The State of the European Union, Vol. 5, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 64.

Shue H. 1997, Eroding Sovereignty: The Advance of Principle, in McKimm/McMahon (eds), The Morality of Nationalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 340.

Shue H. 2004, Limiting Sovereignty, in Welsh (ed.), Humanitarian Intervention and International Relations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 11.

Simma/Paulus 1998, The ‘International Community’: Facing the Challenge of Globalization, 9 European Journal of International Law 266.

Skinner Q. 1989, Language and Political Change, in Ball/Farr/Hanson (eds), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 6.

Snyder F. 1995, Constitutional Law of the European Union, in European Community Law, Collected Courses of the Academy of European Law, Vol. VI:1, Amsterdam: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 41.

Snyder F. 2003, The unfinished constitution of the European Union: principles, processes and culture, in Weiler/Wind (eds), European Constitutionalism Beyond the State, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 55.

Sorensen G. 1999, Sovereignty: Change and Continuity in a Fundamental Institution, 47 Political Studies 590.

Steinberger H. 1997, Sovereignty, in The Encyclopedia of Public International Law, Vol. III, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Teubner G. 1997, ‘Global Bukowina’: Legal Pluralism in the World Society, in Global Law without a State, Aldershot: Ashgate.

Thürer D. 1996, Der Wegfall effektiver Staatsgewalt: ‘The Failed State’, 34 Berichte der deutschen Gesellschaft für Völkerrecht 9.

Thürer D. 1999, The Emergence of Non-Governmental Organizations and Transnational Enterprises in International Law and the Changing Role of the State, in Hoffmann R. (ed.), Non-State Actors as New Subjects of International Law, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 37.

Thürer D. 2000, Modernes Völkerrecht: Ein System im Wandel und Wachstum – Gerechtigkeitsgedanke als Kraft der Veränderungen?, Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 557.

Thürer D. 2001, Recht der internationalen Gemeinschaft und Wandel der Staatlichkeit, in Müller/Aubert (eds), La Constitution suisse, Bern: Stämpfli, 37.

Tomuschat C. 1995, Die internationale Gemeinschaft, Archiv des Völkerrechts 1.

Toth A.G. 1994, Is Subsidiarity Justiciable ?, 19 European Law Review 268.

Tridimas T. 2004, The ECJ and the Draft Constitution: A Supreme Court for the Union ?, Federal Trust Constitutional Online Paper No 05/04. <http://www.fedtrust.co.uk/uploads/constitution/05_04.pdf>

Troper M. 2002, Souveraineté de l’Etat et hiérarchie des normes dans la jurisprudence constitutionnelle. En guise d’introduction: la théorie constitutionnelle et le droit constitutionnel positif, Cahiers du Conseil constitutionnel n° 9.

de Vattel E. 1774, Le droit des gens, ou principes de la loi naturelle, Neuchâtel.

Virally M. 1977, Une pierre d’angle qui résiste au temps: avatars et perennité de l’idée de souveraineté, in Blackhorst R. et al. (eds), Les relations internationales dans un monde en mutation, Geneva: Sijthoff, 179.

Waldron J. 1994, Vagueness in Law and Language, Some Philosophical Issues, 82 California Law Review 509.

Waldron J. 2002, Is the rule of law an essentially contested concept?, 21 Law and Philosophy 137.

Walker R.J.B. 1991, State Sovereignty and the Articulation of Political Space/Time, 20:3 Millenium 445.

Walker/Mendlovitz (eds) 1990, Contending Sovereignties: Redefining Political Community, Boulder: Lynne Reinner.

Walker N. 2000a, Sovereignty and Differentiated Integration in the European Union, in Bankowski/Scott (eds), The European Union and its Legal Order, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 31.

Walker N. 2000b, Flexibility within a Metaconstitutional Frame: Reflections on the Future of Legal Authority in Europe, in De Burca/Scott (eds), Constitutional Change in the EU: Between Uniformity and Flexibility, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Ch. 9.

Walker N. 2002, The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism, 65 Modern Law Review 317.

Walker N. 2003a, Late Sovereignty in the European Union, in Walker N. (ed.), Sovereignty in Transition, Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Walker N. 2003b, Postnational Constitutionalism and the Problems of Translation, in Weiler/Wind (eds), European Constitutionalism Beyond the State, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 27.

Walker N. 2004, After the Constitutional Moment, in Pernice I. (ed.), The Draft Constitutional Treaty, Baden-Baden: Nomos.

Wallace W. 1999, The Sharing of Sovereignty: The European Paradox, 47 Political Studies 503.

Walzer M. 1981, The distribution of membership, in Brown/Shue (eds), Boundaries, National Autonomy and Its Limits, Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield, 1.

Ward I. 1994, In search of European identity, Modern Law Review 315.

Ward I. 1996, The European Constitution and the Nation State, 16 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 161.

Weatherill S. 2002, Is Constitutional Finality Feasible or Desirable? On the Cases for European Constitutionalism and a European Constitution, Constitutionalism Web-Papers, ConWEB No 7/2002. <http://www.qub.ac.uk/schools/SchoolofPoliticsInternationalStudies/FileStore/ConWEBFiles/Filetoupload,5315,en.pdf>

Weiler J.H.H. 1991, The Transformation of Europe, 100 Yale Law Journal 2428.

Weiler J.H.H. 1994, Fin de Siècle Europe, in Dehousse R. (ed.), Europe after Maastricht: an ever closer Union?, Munich: Law Books in Europe, 203.

Weiler J.H.H. 1995, European Democracy and Its Critics – Five Uneasy Pieces, in Cottier/Kaddous (eds), Democracy and Federalism in European Integration, Bern: Stämpfli, 5.

Weiler J.H.H. 1997, The Reformation of European Constitutionalism, 35 Journal of Common Market Studies 97.

Weiler J.H.H. 1998, Europe: the case against the case for statehood, 4 European Law Journal 43.

Weiler J.H.H. 1999, The Constitution of Europe: « Do the new clothes have an emperor ? » and other essays on European integration, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Weiler J.H.H. 2000, The Principle of Constitutional Tolerance, in F. Snyder (ed.), The Europeanisation of Law: The Legal Effects of European Integration, Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Weiler J.H.H. 2002, Federalism and Constitutionalism: Europe’s Sonderweg, in Nicolaidis/Howse (eds), The Federal Vision, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Ch. 2.

Weiler J.H.H. 2003, In defence of the status quo: Europe’s constitutional Sonderweg, in Weiler/Wind (eds), European Constitutionalism Beyond the State, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 7.

Weiler J.H.H. 2004, Ein Christliches Europa, Erkundungsgänge, Salzburg: Anton Pustet.

Weiler/Haltern 1996, The Autonomy of the Community Legal Order: Through the Looking Glass, 37 Harvard Journal of International Law 411.

Weiler/Trachtman 1997, European Constitutionalism and Its Discontents, 17 Northwestern Journal of International Law and Business 354.

Wildhaber L. 1996, Sovereignty and International Law, in Wechselspiel zwischen innen und aussen, Basel: Helbing Liechtenhahn, 19.

De Witte B. 1998, Sovereignty and European Integration: the Weight of Legal Tradition, in Slaughter/Sweet/Weiler (eds), The European Courts and National Courts: Doctrine and Jurisprudence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wittgenstein, L. 1994, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edn, Oxford: Blackwell.

Zuleeg M. 1997, The European Constitution under Constitutional Constraints: The German Scenario, 22 European Law Review 19.

Zürn M. 2000, Democratic Governance beyond the Nation State: The EU and Other International Institutions, 6 European Journal of International Relations 183.


Endnotesto contents list

(*)This is a revised version of an earlier paper published under the title ‘Post-souveraineté ou simple changement de paradigmes? Variations sur un concept essentiellement contestable’, in Balmelli/Borghi/Hildbrand (eds), La souveraineté au XXIème siècle, Fribourg: Editions Interuniversitaires Suisses 2003, pp. 7-58. It is forthcoming in Tierney/Warbrick (eds), The Sovereignty of States and the Sovereignty of International Law, London: BIICL 2005. I presented a preliminary draft of this paper at the Oxford-NYU Exchange Seminar in European Law, 19-20 September, 2002 and would like to thank Josh Holmes, Mattias Kumm, Alexander Somek, Joel Trachtman and Steve Weatherill for their helpful comments. Special thanks are also due to an anonymous referee for EIoP for his numerous comments and critiques.

(1) MacCormick, 1993, 1.

(2) See MacCormick, 1995a, 1995b, 1996, 1997, 1998 and 1999. See also most recently, Kostakopoulou, 2002, 147. See also among others, Bankowski, 1977; Weiler, 1991; Bellamy/Castiglione, 1997; Eleftheriadis, 1996 and 1998; Bankowski/Christodoulidis, 2000; Douglas-Scott, 2002.

(3) See Magnette, 2000 on ‘cooperative sovereignty’; Kostakopoulou, 2002 on ‘floating sovereignty’; Walker, 2003a on ‘late sovereignty’; Maduro, 2003 on ‘contrapunctual sovereignty’; Bellamy, 2003 on ‘mixed sovereignty’; Besson, 2003a and 2003b on ‘cooperative sovereignty’; Besson, 2004b on ‘tamed sovereignty’.

(4) I hereby refer to the term ‘post-national’ as a generic term to mean non-strictly national or international, whether supra-national or merely post-national. It should not be taken to mean that the post-national supplants and replaces national; it can well coexist with it. See e.g. Curtin, 1997.

(5) Walker, 2003a, vii-viii. See also Bellamy, 2003, 179.

(6) One of the first difficulties one encounters in an article about sovereignty is the choice of the disciplinary field. In this paper, I have made the choice of a multiplicity of theoretical points of view in order to reveal the complexity and multiple layers in the roots of sovereignty.

(7) The literature on sovereignty refers interchangeably to the ‘concept’, ‘principle’ or ‘institution’ of sovereignty. See, for instance, Thürer, 1999, 38 ff.; James, 1999; Sorensen, 1999. In this article, I will refer mainly to the concept of sovereignty that underlies the principle or institution we know, without distinguishing the principle from the institution of sovereignty.

(8) See Jackson, 1999b, 431 who compares sovereignty to ‘lego’.

(9) See the expression of Judge Anzilotti in his individual opinion in the case Régime austro-allemand des douanes, CPIJ Series A/B n· 41 (1931), 57. This expression refers to state sovereignty and not to political sovereignty in general.

(10) See Tomuschat, 1995; Simma/Paulus, 1998 on the notion of international community.

(11) See Jackson, 1999b, 436.

(12) See Miller, 1981, 16: ‘Just as we know a camel or a chair when we see one, so we know a sovereign state. It is a political entity which is treated as a sovereign state by other sovereign states.’

(13) See Bodin, 1993, Book I, Chapter VIII, 122-129, 158-161. See also Hobbes, 1999, Ch. 30, 231.

(14) See James, 1986, 6-8; Hinsley, 1986, 117-157.

(15) See e.g. Zürn, 2000, 183; Keating, 2002.

(16) See Müller, 1999a, 137-138.

(17) See Thürer, 1999, 51 ff.; Thürer, 2000, 597 ff.; Tomuschat, 1995, 7; Allot, 1999, 37.

(18) For reasons of clarity, I will limit the scope of this paper to the sovereignty of states and post-national political entities such as the European Union in particular.

(19) See on this concept and for further references, Aalberts, 2004.

(20) See on constitutional conflicts in the EU, Besson, 2003a; Besson, 2004a; Kumm, 1999; Kumm, 2004b; Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004.

(21) See Keating, 2001.

(22) I am using the terms ‘post-national’, ‘post-state’ and ‘post-statist’ interchangeably in this paper.

(23) See in particular Walker, 2002, 334; Falk, 1999, Ch. 2; Koskonniemi, 1991.

(24) See Walker, 2002 and 2003a on constitutional pluralism. See also MacCormick, 1999, 113-121 for the opposition between legal monism (one single legal order that encompasses the national and European legal orders in a hierarchical way) and legal pluralism in the EU (many distinct legal orders that are either radically autonomous or only so under the common umbrella of international law).

(25) See in particular Falk, 1990, 61 ff.; Falk, 2001, 791; Keating, 2001; Shue, 1997, 340 ff.; Wildhaber, 1996, 37; Reisman, 1990, 869. See also the international case-law and in particular the decision of the International Penal Tribunal for Ex-Yugoslavia Appellate Court in the case Prosecutor v. Dusko Tadic (2nd October, 1995), (1996) 35 International Legal Materials 32, n. 97 which mentions the gradual replacement of the ‘state-sovereignty-oriented approach’ by a ‘human-being-oriented approach’. Contra: Jackson, 1999b, 434.

(26) See in particular Schmitter, 1996a.

(27) See Krasner, 1988; Hobe, 1997; Jackson, 1999b, 434 ff.; Virally, 1977, 179.

(28) See e.g. Hinsley, 1986; James, 1986; Krasner, 1988; Jackson, 1990; Bartelson, 1995. See also the special issue of Political Studies 47/1999 called ‘Sovereignty at the Millenium’. See most recently in the European context, Walker, 2003a. For a review of some essays in the book, see Besson, 2004b.

(29) See the exchange between Falk, 1997 and Jackson, 1997.

(30) See on these issues, Van Roermund, 1997, Walker, 2003b and Shaw/Wiener, 1999.

(31) See Kostakopoulou, 2002, 137 f.

(32) See on the post-structuralist dimension of the now well-known opposition between sovereignty, on the one hand, and state, on the other: Hoffman, 1997, 53. See also Laski, 1917 and 1941 who defends the idea of a pluralist society without states.

(33) See MacCormick, 1997, 338.

(34) See Thürer, 2001, n. 40 ff. who speaks of ‘Wandel der Staatlichkeit’.

(35) It is important to distinguish between states and nation-states in this context. The weakening of the nation-state does not imply that of the state tout court.

(36) I am using the terms ‘authority’ and ‘sovereignty’ interchangeably in this paper to refer to normative sovereignty. One way of distinguishing sovereignty from authority is to understand them as referring to the same object but seen from different perspectives: that of the sovereign in the former and that of the subjects in the latter (Besson, 2004a).

(37) Many are those who associate state and sovereignty very closely and hence identify the end or future of state sovereignty with that of sovereignty tout court. See e.g. MacCormick, 1993 and 1999; Wildhaber, 1996, 37 and 46; Hobe, 1997, 147; Thürer, 2001; Aalberts, 2004, 25.

(38) For reasons of space, this paper will concentrate on the concept of sovereignty and will leave aside the different conceptions and fluctuations of the concept of state. On different accounts of the future of the concept of state in Europe and elsewhere, see in particular Shaw, 1999; Hobe, 1997; Schreuer, 1993; Schmitter, 1996a; Thürer, 2001, n. 40 ff.

(39) See Weatherill, 2002 and Weiler, 2003 for a critique of Europe’s pursuit of a formal Constitution.

(40) See Virally, 1977, 195.

(41) On these issues of tyranny and translation of statist concepts in the EU, see Walker, 2003b and Shaw/Wiener, 1999.

(42) See on this notion of ‘floating sovereignty’, Kostakopoulou, 2002, 138 and Walker, 1991, 448. See also Wildhaber, 1996, 49: ‘[Sovereignty] is too relative, too fluctuating, to permit very specific deductions.’

(43) See Krasner, 1988 and 1993; Falk, 2001, 789 on sovereignty’s ‘conceptual migration’; Mayall, 1999, 475; Jackson, 1999b, 433. See Steinberger, 1997, 500 ff. See also Dennert, 1964, 101 ff. For a detailed presentation of the historical origins of sovereignty, see Wildhaber, 1996, 19 ff. and Bartelson, 1995.

(44) See e.g. Walker, 2003a; Bellamy, 2003; Maduro, 2003 for an example of this intentional imprecision in the presentation of the concept’s contours.

(45) See in particular Hinsley, 1986; Virally, 1977, 190; Sorensen, 1999, 597 ff. See a critique by Schmitt, 1996, 26.

(46) See Krasner, 1993, 235 ff. See also Walker/Mendlovitz, 1990; Schmitt, 1996, 25.

(47) See Kostakopoulou, 2002, 147, 155. See also MacCormick, 1999, 133.

(48) See e.g. Walker, 2003a; Bellamy, 2003; Maduro, 2003. See for a review, Besson, 2004b.

(49) Conflicting conceptions of sovereignty can be identified with conflicting claims of sovereignty and vice-versa; the latter rely on the former, but it is difficult to think of the former without matching claims of sovereignty in practice.

(50) See Besson, 2004b on the idea of mutual ‘taming of sovereignty’ through conflict and cooperation.

(51) I will not distinguish between the political and legal uses of the concept of sovereignty which I regard as being the same concept in both fields. Some authors, under a Kelsenian influence, consider erroneously that the legal concept of sovereignty is distinct from the political or moral concept of sovereignty (see Pfersmann, 2001, 31). This approach is belied by the legal practice of normative concepts like sovereignty. This distinction should not be confused, however, with the difference between the concepts of political and legal sovereignty; the latter relates to the object rather than to the nature of the concept. See the discussion under 3.2.1.1.

(52) See Jackson, 1999a, 423 f.

(53) See e.g. Waldron, 2002, 138 ff. on the ‘rule of law’.

(54) On criterial semantics, see Raz, 1998 and Dworkin, 2004.

(55) See Pfersmann, 2001, 31 ff.; Wildhaber, 1996, 24, 40 and 43.

(56) See Waldron, 2002, 140.

(57) See Troper, 2002.

(58) See on these two approaches, Häberle, 1967, 282.

(59) See MacCormick, 1999, 123. See also Jackson, 1999b, 434.

(60) In this sense, the present account differs from a purely constructivist one such as that of Aalberts, 2004, 40.

(61) Walker, 2003a, 6-7.

(62) See Virally, 1977, 179.

(63) See Skinner, 1989 and Farr, 1989.

(64) See on this concept: Gallie, 1956; Waldron, 1994; Waldron, 2002; Dworkin, 1991; Connolly, 1983; MacIntyre, 1973; Gray, 1977; Gray, 1978; Miller, 1983. See on the contestable nature of sovereignty, Sorensen, 1999, 604. See in the European context, Bankowski/Christodoulidis, 2000, 18 who regard sovereignty, but also more generally the European Union as an ‘essentially contested project’. See also Walker, 2000a, 32 and Walker, 2002, 345-346 on the contestable nature of sovereignty in Europe.

(65) See Dworkin, 1991, 90-101 on the relationship between a concept and its conceptions.

(66) See Richmond, 1997, 378-379.

(67) See Wildhaber, 1996, 43 and 45 who speaks of a relative concept.

(68) Aalberts, 2004, 39.

(69)See also Walker, 2003a for a ‘speech-act’ account of sovereignty.

(70) Walker, 2003a, 16-17. See already Richmond, 1997, 379-382.

(71) Howarth, 1995, 127-128, 132; Aalberts, 2004, 40-41.

(72) Gallie, 1956, 169: ‘[these concepts’] proper use inevitably involves endless disputes about their proper use on the part of their users’.

(73) See Hampshire, 1959; Connolly, 1983; MacIntyre, 1973; Gray, 1977; Gray, 1978; Miller, 1983; Ricciardi, 2001.

(74) See Waldron, 1994; Waldron, 2002; Dworkin, 1991; Dworkin, 2004.

(75) See Miller, 1983, 39 ff.

(76) See Raz, 1998.

(77) See Besson, 2005, Ch. 3 for a more detailed account of these concepts.

(78) See Dworkin, 2004.

(79) See Miller, 1983, 39.

(80) A majority of authors still refers, however, to essentially contested concepts by reference to Gallie, 1956.

(81) I disagree with Gray, 1977, 340 ff. on this point.

(82) See Waldron, 1994, 529-530 on these two meanings added by the term ‘essential’ to the contestability of a concept. See also Freeden, 2003, 53.

(83) See Connolly, 1983, 10 ff. See also Hurley, 1989, 46.

(84) See Gallie, 1956, 171 ff.

(85) See Connolly, 1983, 11.

(86) See Hurley, 1989, 47. See also Raz, 1998.

(87) See Connolly, 1983, 7 and 41.

(88) See Waldron, 2002, 153.

(89) See Waldron, 2002, 152.

(90) See Wittgenstein, 1994, 242: ‘If language is to be a means of communication, there must be agreement not only in definitions, but also (queer as it may sound) in judgements’. See more recently, Raz, 1998 on criterial agreement.

(91) See Dworkin, 1991, 72.

(92) See Virally, 1977, 180: ‘Par les valeurs qu’il exprime, par la logique interne qui lui est propre, [le concept de souveraineté] présente un dynamisme dont l’orientation effective dépend du système juridique dans lequel il est utilisé.’ (emphasis added). See also Thürer, 1999, 39, 40: ‘Thus, the basic idea which provides the foundation for our analysis and evaluation of the globalizing evolution of the international system is that, due to its purpose and because of its very nature, state sovereignty represents a value-laden notion. It does in fact, as a concept of present-day international law imply the capacity to realize human rights and other basic values recognized by the international community.’ (emphasis added). See also Jackson, 1999b, 434; Müller, 1999a, 133 ff. See also Walker, 2000a, 33 who regards legal sovereignty as a normative concept which entails an attempt at justifying the law’s authority.

(93) Kelsen, 1926, 255: ‘[Etablir … si tel Etat considéré est souverain ou non n’est pas un] jugement de réalité, mais un jugement de valeur. Plus précisément, il ne s’agit pas d’établir un fait, naturel ou social; mais bien –nous aurons à le démontrer – d’une hypothèse. Discuter sur la souveraineté de l’Etat, c’est raisonner sur des hypothèses de science juridique. Le problème n’est pas un problème d’observation, mais d’interprétation de certains faits; et bien des interprétations sont possibles […]’ (emphasis added).

(94) See Rhonheimer, 1989, 262-263. See also Thürer, 1999, 39, 40 by reference to Müller, 1999a, 132. See also Kelsen, 1961, xvii; Kelsen, 1942, 54-55. See Mayall, 1999, 475. See also Dworkin, 2004 contra Raz, 1998.

(95) In this respect, it is interesting to draw an analogy between the description by Schmitt, 1996 of the paradox of sovereignty, i.e. its normative cum factual dimension, and the double dimension just described of sovereignty qua result and sovereignty qua justification.

(96) See in particular James, 1999, 462. See also Philpott, 1999, 570 ff.

(97) See Sorensen, 1999, 592.

(98) On this issue, see MacCormick, 1995, 95-100 by reference to Foucault in particular; Walker, 2003a, 19-21.

(99) See MacCormick, 1993.

(100) See Kelsen, 1961; Pfersmann, 2001.

(101) On the dissociation of law from the state, see MacCormick, 1999, Chs 1 and 2. Note that MacCormick, 1999a, 128 also dissociates political power from legal sovereignty in his institutional theory of law; it is difficult, however, to see how institutional power implied by legal sovereignty can be distinct from political power in general.

(102) See Teubner, 1997.

(103) See e.g. MacCormick, 1999, 18 ff.; Habermas, 1998.

(104) See e.g. Douglas Scott, 2002, 255. See also Hobbes, 1999 on the dependence of law on the state.

(105) See James, 1999, 462-463. See on sovereignty and constitutionalism, Lindahl, 1997.

(106) See Pfersmann, 2001, 35. See on sovereignty qua competence, Schmitt, 1996, 14, 17. Contra: Wildhaber, 1996, 46 ff.

(107) Contra: Walker, 2000a, 33 who considers political sovereignty as a purely descriptive concept which does not account for the authority of the entity it characterizes, whereas legal sovereignty is a normative concept which does. This position is not tenable, however. It is difficult to see how the same concept can change nature in two different contexts. It remains normative and contestable in both cases, even though the values it protects in those cases and hence its content may differ. Besides, Walker refers to political sovereignty qua measure-concept and later on to legal sovereignty as a threshold concept, thus conflating their functions. Finally, most recently, Walker, 2003a, 19-21 no longer seems to draw a distinction in the content of political and legal sovereignty which he regards as interdependent facets of sovereignty.

(108) See MacCormick, 1999, 25; MacCormick, 1993, 11.

(109) See Walker, 2003a, 19-21; Bellamy, 2003, 171-175; Maduro, 2003, 502.

(110) Walker, 2003a, 19-20.

(111) See Maduro, 2003, 537; Bellamy, 2003, 175.

(112) See Bellamy, 2003; MacCormick, 1997.

(113) Debates about sovereignty in the United Kingdom, for instance, tend to conflate both kinds of sovereignty. See e.g. the Factortame saga and Barber, 2000.

(114) Art. 2(1) of the United Nations Charter guarantees the principle of sovereignty and the equality of states. See Bleckmann, 1994, n. 6.

(115) See MacCormick, 1999, 129 who distinguishes internal from external sovereignty and considers that the latter can exist in the absence of the former.

(116) On this notion of ‘Relationsbegriff’, see Rhonheimer, 1989, 263. See also Loughlin, 2003 on the importance of the relationship between those who govern and those governed. See also Walker, 2003a; Aalberts, 2004, 37.

(117) For instance, it is the German Constitution which in its Art. 23 determines the conditions under which Germany can transfer sovereign competences to the EU. As a consequence, it is internal sovereignty which determines the contours of internal sovereignty, but also of external sovereignty. See e.g. the famous decisions Solange I in 1974, BVerfGE 37, 271; Solange II in 1986, BVerfGE 73, 339; Maastricht Urteil in 1993, BVerfGE 89, 155.

(118) See Pfersmann, 2001, 38-39 on this double determination of external sovereignty. See also Bleckmann, 1994, n. 7 and 11; James, 1999, 464.

(119) See Pfersmann, 2001, 37; Weiler, 2002.

(120) MacCormick, 1999, 133; MacCormick, 1996, 553 who contends that Member States’ external sovereignty is reinforced through European integration.

(121) In fact, Member States’ external sovereignty has progressively been directly reduced by the European Union’s increase of external representation competence. See e.g. Art. I-27 of the Draft Constitutional Treaty on the establishment of an EU Minister of Foreign Affairs.

(122) See Wildhaber, 1996, 39-40, 46. See also Pfersmann, 2001, 34; Bleckmann, 1994, n. 13; Brownlie, 1979, 287. See on the notion of limited international sovereignty, Grotius, 1913, I/III, s. 16, 61; de Vattel, 1774, Book I, Ch. IV, s. 39, p. 52.

(123) See Virally, 1977, 191.

(124) See Bleckmann, 1994, n. 14, 21; Wildhaber, 1996, 39; Virally, 1977, 190-191.

(125) See Walker, 2003a, 4; Walker, 2002.

(126) See Walker, 2000a, 34 who refers to Lee, 1997, 245. See also Pfersmann, 2001, 37.

(127) See Kostakopoulou, 2002, 148.

(128) See Besson, 2005, Ch. 3.

(129) See Lee, 1997, 246 who refers to the test of ‘substantial preponderance of power’, but leaves the question open as to when this degree of substantial preponderance has been reached.

(130) See e.g. Wildhaber, 1996, 49: ‘The member states have delegated some of their sovereign powers, but have retained a sufficient amount of substantive competences in order to continue to qualify as “normal cases” of states. […] [Sovereignty] accepts political or economic dependencies in fact, as long as the discrepancy from the normal case is not too glaring’ (emphasis added). See also Douglas Scott, 2002, 260-261.

(131) See especially Walzer, 1981, 10. See also Sorensen, 1999 who contrasts different ‘constitutive rules’ of sovereignty which do not change, with ‘regulative rules’ of sovereignty which change according to circumstances. See Jackson, 1990, 6 who refers to the Grundnorm of sovereignty.

(132) See the list in Kostakopoulou, 2002, 150 ff.

(133) See e.g. Wildhaber, 1996, 46 ff.

(134) This has been the case in France with monetary sovereignty in particular; the French Constitution and its sovereignty clause had to be revised to be made compatible with the Maastricht Treaty and the European Monetary Union. See on the French ‘Maastricht decisions’, Grewe/Ruiz Fabri, 1992; Olivier, 1994; De Witte, 1998.

(135) See e.g. Walker, 2003a in the European context. See also Lenaerts, 1990 on the absence of reserved competences in the EU: ‘There simply is no nucleus of sovereignty that the Member States can invoke, as such, against the Community.’ (emphasis added).

(136) See e.g. the discussion in James, 1999; Wallace, 1999; Sorensen, 1999.

(137) See Hobbes, 1999, Ch. 18, 127. See also Pogge, 1992, 57; MacCormick, 1999, 130.

(138) See Art. I-9 of the Draft Constitutional Treaty for the principle of conferral.

(139) See Hobe, 1997, 133-134 on this issue. See also Joerges, 2002, 138; Kirchhof, 1998, 940 ff.; Kaufmann, 1999, 814 ff.

(140) See Maduro, 2003, 502 ff. on conflicting sovereignty narratives. On these conflicts of sovereignty and constitutional conflicts more particularly, see Kumm, 2004.

(141) See De Witte, 1998 on proponents of this argument which was for a long time the argument of national authorities and courts in particular.

(142) See Maduro, 2003, 520.

(143) See e.g. Pogge, 1992.

(144) See De Witte, 1998, 303-305 on the contradictions of pooled sovereignty.

(145) Walker, 2003a, 15.

(146) See Pogge, 1992, 59. Contra: MacCormick, 1999, 130.

(147) See Rousseau, 1962.

(148) See Weiler, 2003, 16 on the passé nature of sovereignty claims by contrast to arguments of self-determination and national autonomy or identity.

(149) See e.g. Weiler, 1999, 324 ff.; Weiler/Trachtman, 1997, 377 ff.; Habermas, 2001; Walker, 2003a; Mény, 2003.

(150) See Waldron, 2002, 157 on the ‘rule of law’.

(151) Bankowski/Christodoulidis, 2000, 24 and 30.

(152) See Estella, 2002, 10, 38.

(153) See e.g. Douglas Scott, 2002, 173 n. 86; Müller, 1999b, 167 ff.; Lecheler, 1992; Bermann, 1994; Peterson, 1994; MacCormick, 1995a; MacCormick, 1997; De Burca, 1999; Follesdal, 1998; Blichner/Sangolt, 1994; Estella, 2002; Bankowski, 1977; Emiliou, 1992; Toth, 1994; Henkel, 2002; Jones, 1997; Kumm, 2004a; Marquardt, 1994.

(154) See on this point, Blichner/Sangolt, 1994, 286. See in the European context, Peterson, 1994, 116; Preuss, 1999, 426.

(155) See Ward, 1996, 164.

(156) See Weiler, 2004.

(157) See on the principle in general, Tomuschat, 1995, 18; Hobe, 1997, 149.

(158) Despite the addition of the Subsidiarity Protocol to the Amsterdam Treaty and its consolidation in the Draft Constitutional Treaty, the principle has not yet had the impact it deserves at EU level. See Estella, 2002, 6-7. See also Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004; Tridimas, 2004.

(159) See Müller, 1999b, 171 on the relationship of complementarity between sovereignty and subsidiarity.

(160) See Bermann, 1994, 366: ‘[subsidiarity] starts off precisely where the conventional tools of constitutional federalism leave off and where legislative politics is ordinarily thought to begin.’ Contra Follesdal, 1998, it is important to understand therefore that the principle of subsidiarity is an efficiency principle applied to political organization; it need not be justified independently from the political principles whose best application it ensures, except qua efficiency test.

(161) See Hobe, 1997, 148.

(162) See in the human rights context, Ermacora, 1966, 689.

(163) See Waldron, 2002, 164.

(164) MacCormick, 1999, 142.

(165) See MacCormick, 1999, 135.

(166) On this question, see Besson, 2004a; Follesdal, 2000, 105.

(167) See Esher, 1999, 117; Hobe, 1997, 152-153; Virally, 1977, 193. See also Thürer, 2000, 592.

(168) See Habermas, 2001 on this post-national constellation and its impact on the cooperation between national states.

(169) See Tomuschat, 1995, 6-7; Thürer, 2000, 592.

(170) See MacCormick, 1999, 104, 131. See also Richmond, 1997.

(171) See Bleckmann, 1994, n. 36. See also Esher, 1999, 117 ff.; Thürer,1999, 58; Magnette, 2000; Besson, 2003a; Besson, 2004a; Besson, 2004b.

(172) On this obligation to intervene based on sovereignty qua right, see Shue, 2004.

(173) See Besson 2004a, 271. See also Richmond, 1997, 415-417.

(174) See on the dynamism of sovereignty, Virally, 1977, 180.

(175) See Richmond, 1997, 417 and MacCormick, 1999, 113-121 on ‘soft pluralism’ or ‘pluralist monism’ and the coexistence of independent albeit conflicting viewpoints between distinct legal orders in the European context.

(176) See Walker, 2002, 336 ff.; Walker, 2003a; Maduro, 2003.

(177) On the end of unified because personified sovereignty in the European Union, see Cohen/Sabel, 2003.

(178) Bleckmann, 1994, n. 30 et 37.

(179) See Müller, 1999a, 136 ff. who refers to Huber, 1929, 17.

(180) When a sovereign state is democratic, one of the values sovereignty contributes to protecting is democracy. Hence current fears about the democratic deficit in Europe. See Müller, 1999b, 170 ff. See also James, 1999, 473.

(181) See MacCormick, 1999, 125 who associates sovereignty to national self-determination, and emphasizes the importance of the question of nationalism for debates about the future of sovereignty in Europe. See also Weiler, 2004, 149-152.

(182) See Thürer, 1999, 39.

(183) See Jackson, 1999b, 454.

(184) See Virally, 1977, 191; Tomuschat, 1995, 20. See also Huber, 1929, 17 on the Palma case.

(185) See Müller, 1999a, 132: ‘Im folgenden Gedankengang möchte ich zu einem Souveränitätsverständnis hinführen, das die Anforderungen des internationalen Menschenrechtsschutzes nicht bloss als notwendige, gleichsam zähmende Schranke staatlicher Souveränität versteht; vielmehr ist die Gewährleistung elementarer Menschenrechtsgehalte heute als ein konstitutives Element staatlicher Souveränität, als eine ihr immanente Aufgabe zu qualifizieren.’ (emphasis added). See also Bleckmann, 1994, n. 21.

(186) See Müller, 1999a, 139; Thürer, 1996, 15; Reisman, 1990, 872.

(187) See Thürer, 2000, 578; Thürer, 1999, 39. See also Müller, 1999a, 120, 138.

(188) See Besson, 2003c.

(189) Contra: MacCormick, 1999, 125 ff.

(190) See Hobe, 1997, 133 on all potential transfers of competences allowed by Art. 24 of the German Basic Law, within the limits of the principle of the intangibility of certain fundamental rights of Art. 79 and on the notion of ‘open state’ which allows the state to intervene and to be intervened into without limits in international cooperation. See also Zuleeg, 1997 on the concept of ‘open statehood’. This approach to Art. 24 is not uncontroversial, however. In 1993, when the Maastricht Treaty was ratified, the German Federal Constitutional Court had to decide on the conformity of the Treaty with the German Basic Law and the principle of national sovereignty in particular. According to the claimants, Germany could not transfer sovereign competences to the EU so long as the latter was not sufficiently democratic. In its Maastricht-Urteil, the Court rejected that argument on the grounds that no fundamental sovereign competence had been transferred (Judgement of 1993, BVerfGE 89, 155). This seems to indicate a distinction between ordinary transferable competences of sovereignty and more fundamental competences which cannot be transferred at all.

(191) See Weiler, 1997, 112 ff.; MacCormick, 1999, 135.

(192) See Maduro, 2002 on the similar idea of competition among national and European democracies.

(193) See Thürer, 1996 on ‘failed states’. The idea of ‘failed sovereign’ seems to capture the problem more adequately in a post-Westphalian world where states are no longer the only political entities in charge.

(194) See Annan, 1999, 6: ‘Sovereignty implies responsibility, not just power’.

(195) On the obligation to intervene as an intrinsic element of sovereignty, see Shue, 2004. See also Shue, 2004 and Bull, 1966 on collective intervention as the only legitimate way of limiting a collectively recognized sovereign.

(196) See Dworkin, 1991, 72.

(197) Contra: Sorensen, 1999, 591 ff.

(198) On these issues, see Besson, 2005, Ch. 3. See on conceptual change tout court: Raz, 2001, 171-172. See on conceptual change and sovereignty: Virally, 1977, 180; Reisman, 1990, 869 ff.; Mayall, 1999, 501.

(199) See Schreuer, 1993, 453.

(200) See Jackson, 1990, 6.

(201) See Krasner, 1993, 235.

(202) See Bankowski/Christodoulidis, 2000, 23. See also Kostakopoulou, 2002, 148.

(203) See James, 1999, 457.

(204) See Falk, 2001, 791.

(205) See Krasner, 1999.

(206) See Connolly, 1983, 213. See Arendt, 1973, 220.

(207) See Falk, 2001, 789; Jackson, 1999b, 433; Virally, 1977, 179.

(208) See Sorensen, 1999, 604; Falk, 2001, 791; Wildhaber, 1996, 49. See also Besson, 2004a. See more generally Waldron, 2002, 162.

(209) See Bleckmann, 1994, n. 42. See also Loughlin, 2003 and Biersteker/Weber, 1996 on sovereignty qua social construction and integral part of the political and legal discourse. See also Aalberts, 2004.

(210) See Falk, 2001, 791; Virally, 1977, 195. Contra: Wildhaber, 1996, 24 et 37. One can actually observe a tendency to conceptual fragmentation in practice, as people discuss concepts like democracy or human rights individually rather than together under the umbrella of sovereignty.

(211) I have addressed this issue in more detail in Besson, 2000; Besson, 2003a; Besson, 2004a; Besson, 2004b.

(212) Interestingly, by contrast to what has been the case elsewhere, the issue of sovereignty did not raise much controversy in the EU before the early 1990s; the idea of mere delegation of the exercize of national sovereignty to the EU was largely predominant and for a long time EU authorities were reluctant to express their own sovereignty claims. See De Witte, 1998, 281-293.

(213) See the exchange between Weiler/Haltern, 1996 and Schilling, 1996a; Schilling, 1996b.

(214) See von Bogdandy, 2000; Schmitter, 1996b; Magnette, 2000. See also the exchange between Weiler, 1998 and Mancini, 1998.

(215) Although EU authorities have always been reluctant to express their own sovereignty claims, the ECJ has been more assertive in its development of the doctrine of supremacy as opposed to sovereignty. See De Burca, 2003.

(216) See on constitutional conflicts in the EU, Besson, 2003a; Kumm, 1999; Kumm, 2004b; Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004.

(217) This principle is actually nuanced by Art. I-9 and the principle of conferral.

(218) Ward, 1994; Richmond, 1997.

(219) See Maduro, 2003, 502 ff. on these two narratives.

(220) See Phelan, 1997.

(221) See among national sovereigntists, Grimm, 1995.

(222) See among EU sovereigntists, Mancini, 1998 and maybe Habermas, 2001.

(223) See MacCormick 1999, 113 ff. who seems to have moved away from post-sovereignty (compare MacCormick, 1993) to a more unitary conception of sovereignty under the influence of Richmond, 1997, in defending his ‘pluralist monism’ or ‘soft monism’ which accommodates separate legal orders under the monist and sovereign umbrella of international law.

(224) See Pernice, 2002’s multilevel constitutionalism in whose framework the ultimate authority remains EU-centred.

(225) Traces of unitary sovereignty may also be found in Joseph Weiler’s idea of a European ‘conseil constitutionnel’ whose main flavour is resolutely European, thus prima facie contradicting his principle of constitutional tolerance (Weiler, 1999; Weiler, 2003) or finally, in Mattias Kumm’s and Victor Ferreres-Comella’s idea of a legal framework of cooperation whose cooperative dimension is undermined by the legal and unitary nature of the framework of cooperation they propose to entrench in the European Constitutional Treaty (Kumm, 2004b; Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004).

(226) Walker, 2003a, 14.

(227) See Craig, 2001; Walker, 2004. See also Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004 on the limits of Art. I-10. See also Walker, 2004 on the Draft Constitutional Treaty’s limiting effect on the choice between intergovernmentalism (art. I-5 or I-9) and federalism (Art. I-10).

(228) See De Witte, 1998, 303-303 on the contradictions of pooled sovereignty.

(229) Walker, 2003a, 15.

(230) See e.g. Pescatore, 1970 in the EU and Pogge, 1992 at the global level.

(231) See Shaw/Wiener, 1999, 78 on this ‘touch of stateness’.

(232) See MacCormick 1993. Note that he now seems to have moved away from post-sovereignty to a more unitary conception of sovereignty (MacCormick 1999, 113 ff.).

(233) Walker, 2003a, viii.

(234) See Weiler, 2003, 16.

(235) See Shaw, 2003b; Jessurun D’Oliveira, 1999.

(236) See on the French ‘Maastricht decisions’, Grewe/Ruiz Fabri, 1992; Olivier, 1994.

(237) See the German case BVerwGE 103, 301 of 30.01.1996, NJW 1996 2173 and the ECJ case C-285/98 Tanja Kreil v. Federal Republic of Germany [2000] ECR I-69.

(238) See De Witte, 1998, 304; Walker, 2003a, 16-17. See also Richmond, 1997, 379-382.

(239) See Weiler, 2004, 149-152 on these reactionary modern reactions to post-modern Angst about the European Union.

(240) Of course, this fourth conception of sovereignty may be understood as complementary to the other conceptions.

(241) See on a similar conception, Magnette, 2000, 155-159, 161-166; Besson, 2003a; Besson, 2003b; Besson, 2004a; Besson, 2004b.

(242) See Virally, 1977, 193; Esher, 1999, 117 ff.; Mayall, 1999, 501.

(243) See Besson 2004a, 278. See also Aziz, 2003, 279.

(244) Maduro, 2003, 511-520.

(245) Walker, 2003a, 27.

(246) See Walker, 2003a, 27-30 on the constructive effect of reflexivity. See also Besson 2004a, 275-276.

(247) See Besson 2004a, 260-261.

(248) Maduro, 2003, 524-531. There is a certain amount of circularity in Maduro’s account: he justifies duties of coherence on grounds of competitive sovereignty, but argues for competitive sovereignty on grounds of those very duties (Maduro, 2003, 511-520). See by contrast Besson 2004a and Besson, 2005, Ch. 11 for a non sovereignty-based justification of the principle of coherence.

(249) Maduro, 2003, 534 (emphasis added).

(250) Maduro, 2003, 524.

(251) Maduro, 2003, 533-534.

(252) Besson 2004a, 269.

(253) Bellamy, 2003, 189.

(254) See for a proposal of a legal and unifying institutional framework of collaboration, Kumm, 2004b; Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004. See also, although in another context, MacCormick, 1999 on the international legal framework. See, finally, Weiler, 1999 on a European ‘Conseil constitutionnel’, although this seems to be in contradiction with his constitutional tolerance principle (Weiler, 2003).

(255) MacCormick, 1999 on radical pluralism.

(256) See Besson, 2004a.

(257) See Weiler, 2003 on the European virtue of ‘constitutional tolerance’.

(258) See also Besson 2004a, 278-279; Besson 2003a on other advantages of cooperative sovereignty.

(259) See Bellamy/Castiglione, 2004 on polity legitimacy as opposed to regime legitimacy. See also Maduro, 2002.

(260) Walker, 2003a, 31-32.

(261) See Kumm, 1999, 353, 362.

(262) See Kumm, 1999. See Maduro, 2003’s critique of Kumm.

(263) See Weiler/Haltern, 1996; MacCormick, 1999; Besson, 2000.

(264) See Weiler/Trachtman, 1997, 391.

(265) See Besson, 2004a, 277-278.

(266) See Besson, 2003a. See also Aziz, 2003; Kumm, 1999, 369 on what the German Federal Constitutional Court calls the ‘cooperation relationship’ in the Maastricht Urteil.

(267) See Kumm, 1999, 351.

(268) See Schwarze, 2000; Weatherill, 2002. See e.g. the signal given by the ECJ in Case C-285/98 Tanja Kreil c. Federal Republic of Germany [2000] ECR I-69 and by the German Federal Constitutional Court in the Bananas case: BVerfGE 2 BvL 1/97 7.6.2000, EuZW 2000, 702. See more generally Besson, 2004a, 277-278 with further references.

(269) See Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004 on the indirect taming impact of Art. I-10 of the Draft Constitutional Treaty on the likelihood of future constitutional conflicts.

(270) See Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004 on this prognosis.

(271) See Kumm, 2004b and Kumm/Ferreres-Comella, 2004 for such a proposal.

(272) Maduro, 2003, 522-523. See also Weiler, 2003 on European multilayered ‘constitutional laboratories’.

(273) According to Maduro, 2002, this democratic reinforcement function of cooperative sovereignty is actually constitutive of the legitimacy of the European polity itself.

(274) See Weiler, 1997, 112 ff.; MacCormick, 1999, 135. See also Maduro, 2002 on the competition among national and European democracies and the corresponding improvement of national and European democratic standards.

(275) See Mény, 2003; Moravcsik, 2002 for this critique.

(276) See Nicolaidis, 2003 on European demoi-cracy. See also Bellamy, 2003, 188-189.

(277) See De Witte, 1998; Bellamy, 2003; Maduro, 2003.

(278) See e.g. Weiler, 1995; Maduro, 2002; Mény, 2003.

(279) See Blichner, 2000, 142 ff. See also Miller/Ware, 1996 on national parliaments’ perspective and Bond, 1997 on the European Parliament’s perspective.

(280) See in particular Blichner, 2000.

(281) See Besson, 2004a, 278-279.

(282) See Maduro, 2002 and Maduro, 2003.

(283) See Habermas, 2001 on this point.

(284) See Cohen/Sabel, 2003 on constitutionalism qua activity rather than qua set of enumerated powers and rights. See also Snyder, 1995, 56-59; Snyder, 2003, 62 ff.

(285) For an analysis of the different conceptions of European constitutionalism, Walker, 2004.

(286) See e.g. Chalmers, 1997, 180; Mortelmans, 1996, 42-43.

(287) See Snyder, 1995, 100 on this point.

(288) See Besson, 2004a, 279-280.

(289) Maduro, 2003, 522-523.

(290) Maduro, 2003, 535-536.

(291) See Weiler, 2003 and Weiler, 2000. See also Besson 2004a, 279-280.

(292) See Craig, 2001 and Walker, 2004.

(293) See Shaw, 2001; Shaw, 2003a.

(294) For a discussion of this European ‘constitutional moment’, see Walker, 2004.


©2004 by Samantha Besson
formated and tagged by K.H., 15.09.2004